Skip to main content
Log in

Contextualism about object-seeing

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When is seeing part of an object enough to qualify as seeing the object itself? For instance, is seeing a cat’s tail enough to qualify as seeing the cat itself? I argue that whether a subject qualifies as seeing a given object varies with the context of the ascriber. Having made an initial case for the context-sensitivity of object-seeing, I then address the contention that it is merely a feature of the ordinary notion. I argue that the notions of object-seeing that earn their explanatory keep in both vision science and the philosophy of perception are context-sensitive as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For some similar cases, see Dretske (1969, 27) and Neta (2007).

  2. Dretske (1969, 28) seems to suggest a view along these lines, although he merely suggests it in passing without defending or clarifying the view in any detail. More recently, Neta (2007) has also defended a view along the lines of (CS); he too does not go beyond cases. Clarke (1965) defends a view that departs from (CS) in one important way. According to him, sees is a “unit concept.” A unit concept F only applies to O in a given context if O is the unit determined by that context, and it only applies to a certain amount of O (e.g. its facing surface) if that amount is the unit determined by the given context. It follows that if F applies to O in context C, then it does not apply to any part of O; whereas, if it applies to part of O then it does not apply to O itself. Thus, in the case of seeing, Clarke’s view is that if O has been singled out as “the relevant unit” then the subject counts as seeing O; whereas, if the facing surface of O, say P, has been singled out then the subject only counts as seeing P (not O). The problem with Clarke’s view is that it just does not fit the linguistic data. Seeing-ascriptions of the following sort are commonplace: “I see Bill and all of his toes”; “She saw the house and its beautiful façade.”

  3. See Kennedy (1999) for a detailed discussion of scalar analyses.

  4. It is for this reason that Stanley’s (2004, 2005) arguments against the view that ‘knows’ exhibits the same kind of context-sensitivity as gradable terms such as ‘tall’ do not threaten the contextualist account of ‘sees’ that I’m defending here.

  5. See Phillips (2014) for a more detailed discussion of the notion of high integration, as well as the way in which Kriegel deploys it.

  6. See DeRose (2009, 112–17) for a similar point in defense of the claim that the apparent context-sensitivity of ‘knows’ cannot be explained away in terms of implicatures.

  7. See Strawson (1959) for a version of this view.

  8. There may well be reasons for thinking that which properties one represents (in thought or perception) is a context-sensitive affair. However, it is extremely plausible that the demonstrative element of Roger’s thought refers to the crocodile, not its tail. Claiming that which property his thought counts as representing is a context-sensitive affair does nothing to alter that point. Thus, in order to avoid the worries mentioned above we still need to posit a context-invariant reference-fixing mechanism for his thought’s demonstrative element.

  9. For some non-descriptivist reference-fixing mechanisms that are compatible with the claim that we refer, in thought, to the objects we perceive in a context-invariant fashion, see Campbell (2002) and Dickie (2011).

  10. Once again, I will not argue for the view that which properties are represented in perception (or thought) is a context-invariant affair. In brief, though, one reason for denying that which properties are represented in perception is a context-sensitive affair is that the phenomenal character of a perceptual experience is plausibly constituted by those facts concerning which properties it represents. Given that the phenomenal character of my experience does not seem to vary with the interests of ascribers, this suggests that which properties my experience represents does not vary in this way either. But that is a topic for another paper.

  11. This appears to be Burge’s view of seeing (2009, 31, 2010, 456).

  12. See Putnam (1975) and Kripke (1980).

  13. See Nanay (2010, 2011, 2012, 2015) for a defense of this view.

  14. Grice (1961) is the locus classicus of causal theories of perception. See Gates (1996) for a compelling argument that that no purely informational-causal account of reference (be it perceptual or cognitive) can avoid the kind of indeterminacy described above.

  15. See Clark (2006) and Dickie (2010) for similar points.

  16. It is well known that top-down attention can drive the selection of targets. See Pylyshyn and Annan (2006) for a discussion.

References

  • Block, N. (2013). The grain of vision and the grain of attention. Thought, 1, 170–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2014). Seeing-as in the light of vision science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(3), 560–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2009). Five theses on de re states and attitudes. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi (Eds.), The philosophy of David Kaplan (pp. 246–316). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Attention and inscrutability: A commentary on John Campbell. Reference and consciousness, for the Pacific APA Meeting, Pasadena, California, 2004, vol. 127, pp. 167–93.

  • Clarke, T. (1965). Seeing surfaces and physical objects. In M. Black (Ed.), Philosophy in America (pp. 98–114). Paris: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dickie, I. (2010). We are acquainted with ordinary things. In R. Jeshion (Ed.), New essays on singular thought (pp. 213–245). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dickie, I. (2011). Visual attention fixes demonstrative reference by eliminating referential luck. In C. Mole, D. Smithies, & W. Wu (Eds.), Attention: Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 292–322). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gates, G. (1996). The price of information. Synthese, 107(3), 325–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 35, pp. 121–68.

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A representative theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (1999). Projecting the adjective: The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2009). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (1998). Biological universals and the nature of fear. Journal of Philosophy, 95, 105–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). A modal theory of function. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 412–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2011). Function, modality and mental content. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 32, 84–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2012). Function attribution depends on the explanatory context. Journal of Philosophy, 109, 623–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2015). The representationalism versus relationism debate: explanatory contextualism about perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 23(2), 321–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neta, R. (2007). Contextualism and a puzzle about seeing. Philosophical Studies, 134(1), 53–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, B. (2014). Indirect representation and the self-representational theory of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 167(2), 273–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 215–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2001). Visual indexes, preconceptual objects, and situated vision. Cognition, 80(1/2), 127–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2003). Seeing and visualizing: It’s not what you think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2006). Some puzzling findings in multiple object tracking (MOT): II. Inhibition of moving nontargets. Visual Cognition, 14(2), 175–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2007). Things and places: How the mind connects with the world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z., & Annan, V. (2006). Dynamics of target selection in multiple object tracking (MOT). Spatial Vision, 19, 485–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). How does phenomenology constrain object-seeing? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(3), 429–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2004). On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 119–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the following people for useful input on earlier versions of this paper: Jacob Berger, Tony Dardis, Ryan DeChant, Jørgen Dyrstad, Nemira Gasiunas, Grace Helton, Zoe Jenkin, Uriah Kriegel, Laura Larocca, Myrto Mylopoulus, David Neely, Gary Ostertag, Jesse Prinz, Jake Quilty-Dunn, David Rosenthal, Jonathan Schaffer, and Elmar Geir Unnsteinsson. I’m also grateful to audiences at the CUNY Cognitive Science Speaker Series, L’Institut Jean Nicod, and the University of Toronto.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ben Phillips.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Phillips, B. Contextualism about object-seeing. Philos Stud 173, 2377–2396 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0619-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0619-6

Keywords

Navigation