Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Imagery, expression, and metaphor

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Metaphorical utterances are construed as falling into two broad categories, in one of which are cases amenable to analysis in terms of semantic content, speaker meaning, and satisfaction conditions, and where image-construction is permissible but not mandatory. I call these image-permitting metaphors, and contrast them with image-demanding metaphors (IDM’s) comprising a second category and whose understanding mandates the construction of a mental image. This construction, I suggest, is spontaneous, is not restricted to visual imagery, and its result is typically somatically marked sensu Damasio. IDM’s are characteristically used in service of self-expression, and thereby in the elicitation of empathy. Even so, IDM’s may reasonably provoke banter over the aptness of the imagery they evoke.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Zwaan et al. (2002, 2004) and Wassenberg and Zwaan (2010), provide experimental evidence suggesting that even idioms such as these activate mental imagery. However, we do not yet know that such imagery is required for utterance interpretation.

  2. To say that a metaphor requires that the hearer construct an image in order to comprehend the speaker, is not to say that there is a particular image that must be so constructed. Instead, anything within a vaguely specifiable range will do. Accordingly, we can reliably identify cartoon-like images of one person sweeping a floor with another, and of a person throwing their cap over a wall on the other side of which is something vast and mysterious. Further, in what follows we will not need to take sides on the dispute over the nature of mental imagery. Whether such images are sui generis phenomena or instead reducible to, say, sentences in the language of thought, need not be settled here. Instead, we assume only that speakers do in fact form mental images that they on occasion use in utterance interpretation. (See Kind 2001 for further discussion.) Likewise, the present discussion remains neutral on the extent to which mental imagery is embodied. (Gibbs and Berg 2002 contend that much mental imagery is embodied.).

  3. K. Rexroth, ‘Falling Leaves and Early Snow,’ from The Collected Shorter Poems (New Directions Publishing, 1996).

  4. The position I defend in this essay is in broad agreement with that espoused in Carston (2010), but differs in a number of details. For instance, Carston remarks (2010, p. 300) that all metaphors require contemplation of an image, writing, “…in my view, full understanding of any metaphor involves both a propositional/conceptual component and an imagistic component, though the relative weight and strength of each of these varies greatly from case to case.” We do not adopt that view here. So too, Carston suggests (ibid, p. 317) that metaphors that rely heavily on imagery fall outside the domain of pragmatics because they are not driven by reflexive communicative intentions. By contrast, because I take imagistic metaphors to be characteristically in the service of self-expression, which I take in turn to fall within the domain of signaling (see Sect. 2), I take these kinds of metaphor to fall within pragmatics.

  5. Just as a speaker might utter a sentence with the intention only of expressing a proposition rather than performing an illocution, it also seems possible for a speaker to utter an IPM with a similar sub-illocutionary purpose.

  6. Space limitations preclude discussion of the neurological aspects of the somatic marker hypothesis. Damasio (1995) and subsequent work by his team of collaborators provide ample discussion of this dimension of the hypothesis.

  7. A reviewer of an earlier draft of this essay suggested that talk of a propositional content being conversationally implicated sounds contradictory. The reason given for this seems to be that propositional contents only appear as part of what is said, rather than of what is implicated. This view rests on a confusion. For while it may be that there is more indeterminacy in what is implicated than in what is said, it is still the case that any putative determination of what is implicated will refer to a semantic content, be it propositional, interrogative, imperative, or of a type corresponding to a fourth, more exotic grammatical mood.

  8. “The only way of expressing emotion in the form of art is by finding an “objective correlative”; in other words, a set of objects, a situation, a chain of events which shall be the formula of that particular emotion; such that when the external facts, which must terminate in sensory experience, are given, the emotion is immediately evoked.” From Eliot, ‘Hamlet and his Problems,’ in Eliot (1930).

References

  • Adolphs, R. (2003). Cognitive neuroscience of human social behavior. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 165–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, L. (2006). Metaphor in the mind: The cognition of metaphor. Philosophy Compass, 1, 154–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, L. (2013). Metaphor and varieties of meaning. In Lepore & Ludwig (Eds.), Blackwell companion to Davidson (pp. 361–378). Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2010). Metaphor: Ad hoc concepts, literal meaning and mental images. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society, Vol. CX, (pp. 295–321).

  • Damasio, A. (1995). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason and the human brain. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1978). What metaphors mean. In S. Sacks (Ed.), On metaphor. Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. (2003). Meaning, expression and thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eliot, T. S. (1930). The sacred wood: Essays on poetry and criticism. New York: Alfred A Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R., & Berg, E. (2002). Mental imagery and embodied activity. Journal of Mental Imagery, 26, 1030.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. (2007). Self-expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. (2008). Empathy, expression and what artworks have to teach. In G. Hagberg (Ed.), Art and ethical criticism (pp. 95–122). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. (2014). Speech acts. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/speech-acts/.

  • Green, M. (2016). Expressing, showing, and representing. In C. Abell & J. Smith (Eds.), Emotional expression: Philosophical, psychological, and legal perspectives. Cambridge.

  • Grice, P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2001). Putting the image back in imagination. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Stone, M. (2010). Against metaphorical meaning. Topoi, 29, 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Stone, M. (2014). Philosophical investigations into figurative speech, metaphor and irony. Protosociology: An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research, 31, 75–87.

  • Lepore, E., & Stone, M. (2015). Imagination and convention: Distinguishing grammar and inference in language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S. (1992). Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 509–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M., & Camp, L. (2008). Metaphor. In Lepore & Smith (Eds.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of language (pp. 845–863). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). Metaphor. In P. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (2008). A deflationary account of metaphors. In R. Gibbs (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of metaphor and thought (pp. 84–108). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, K., & Eddy, P. (2013). Women and academic leadership: leaning out. Chronicle of Higher Education. http://chronicle.com/article/WomenAcademic-Leadership-/143503/.

  • Wassenberg, S., & Zwaan, R. (2010). Readers routinely represent implied object rotation: The role of visual experience. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63, 1665–1670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R., Madden, C., Yaxley, R., & Aveyard, M. (2004). Moving words: Dynamic representations in language comprehension. Cognitive Science, 28, 611–619.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R., Madden, C., Yaxley, R., Aveyard, M., Stanfield, R., & Yaxley, R. (2002). Language comprehenders mentally represent the shapes of objects. Psychological Science, 13, 168–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to all three audiences, and particularly to Nick Allott, Liz Camp, Robyn Carston, Joel Martinez, Jay Odenbaugh, Mihaela Popa, and Dierdre Wilson, for their insights. I am also grateful to two anonymous referees for this journal for their detailed and insightful comments on an earlier draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mitchell Green.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Green, M. Imagery, expression, and metaphor. Philos Stud 174, 33–46 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0607-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0607-x

Keywords

Navigation