Philosophical Studies

, Volume 173, Issue 5, pp 1335–1359 | Cite as

Three kinds of worlds and two kinds of truth

Article

Abstract

This paper argues for three kinds of possible worlds: Wittgensteinian totalities of facts, Lewisian worlds or universes, concrete objects of maximal essence, and the world, a concrete object of minimal essence. It moreover explains that correspondence truth applies to Wittgensteinian totalities and pragmatic truth to Lewisian universes. And it finally argues that this conceptualization lays proper foundations to two-dimensional semantics.

Keywords

Possible worlds Metaphyiscal possiblity Epistemic possibility Correspondence truth Pragmatic truth Essentialism Two-dimensional semantics 

References

  1. Adams, R. M. (1979). Primitive thisness and primitve identity. Journal of Philosophy, 76, 5–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Benkewitz, W. (2011). Wahrnehmen, Glauben und Gegenstände, Eine historisch-systematische Untersuchung. Heidelberg: Synchron.Google Scholar
  4. Carnap, R. (1947), Meaning and necessity (2nd extended ed. 1956). Chicago University Press: Chicago.Google Scholar
  5. Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Chalmers, D. J. (2006). The foundations of two-dimensional semantics. In M. García-Carpintero & J. Macià (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics (pp. 55–140). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Chalmers, D. J. (2012). Constructing the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Chalmers, D. J., & Jackson, F. (2001). Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review, 110, 315–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Ellis, B. (1990). Truth and objectivity. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  10. Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fine, K. (2005). Modality and tense. Philosophical papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics. The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Forbes, G. (1985). The metaphysics of modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Haas-Spohn, U. (1995). Versteckte Indexikalität und subjektive Bedeutung. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. English translation available at: http://www.uni-konstanz.de/philosophie/files/haas-spohn_-versteckte_indexikalitaet_und_subjektive_bedeutung.pdf
  15. Haas-Spohn, U., & Spohn, W. (2001). Concepts are beliefs about essences. In A. Newen, U. Nortmann, & R. Stuhlmann-Laeisz (Eds.), Building on Frege. New essays on sense, content, and concept (pp. 287–316). Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  16. Halbach, V. (2011). Axiomatic theories of truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  18. Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 277–322). Amsterdam: Amsterdam Centre.Google Scholar
  19. Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives. An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In J. Almog, J., Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
  20. Kaplan, D. (1979). On the logic of demonstratives. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 81–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson, & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355 + 763–769). Dordrecht: Reidel; ext. ed.: Oxford: Blackwell 1980.Google Scholar
  22. Kukla, A. (1996). Does every theory have empirically equivalent rivals? Erkenntnis, 44, 137–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Künne, W. (2003). Conceptions of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Leitgeb, H., & Ladyman, J. (2008). Criteria of identity and structuralist ontology. Philosophia Mathematica, 16, 388–396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Lewis, D. (1968). Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 113–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lewis, D. (1979). Attitudes De Dicto and De Se. Philosophical Review, 88, 513–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lewis, D. (1980). Index, context, and content. In S. Kanger & S. Öhman (Eds.), Philosophy and grammar (pp. 79–100). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  29. Linnebo, Ø., & Muller, F. A. (2013). On witness-discernibility of elementary particles. Erkenntnis, 78, 1133–1142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Mackie, P. (2006). How things might have been. Individuals, kinds, and essential properties. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Montague, R. (1970). Universal grammar. Theoria 36, 373–398; Also in Montague, R. (1974). In R. H. Thomason (Ed.), Formal philosophy (pp. 222–246). New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Perry, J. (1980). A problem about continued belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61(1980), 317–332.Google Scholar
  33. Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of, meaning. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Philosophical papers, vol. 2: Mind, language and reality (pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Putnam, H. (1981). Reason truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Rescher, N. (1973). The coherence theory of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of matheatmics. Structure and ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Spohn, W. (1997a). Über die Gegenstände des Glaubens. In G. Meggle (Ed.), Analyomen 2. Proceedings of the 2nd conference "Perspectives in analytical philosophy". Logic, epistemology, philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 291–321). Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  38. Spohn, W. (1997b). The character of color predicates: A materialist view. In W. Künne, A. Newen, & M. Anduschus (Eds.), Direct reference, indexicality and propositional attitudes (pp. 351–379). Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  39. Spohn, W. (2007). How are mathematical objects constituted? A structuralist answer. In H. Bohse & S. Walter (Eds.), Proceedings of the 6th congress of the Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie (pp. 106–119). Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  40. Spohn, W. (2008). Causation, coherence, and concepts. A collection of essays. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief. Ranking theory and its philosophical applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Spohn, W. (2015). Conditionals: A unified ranking-theoretic perspective. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(1), 1–30.Google Scholar
  43. Stalnaker, R. C. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, vol. 9: Pragmatics (pp. 315–332). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  44. Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of KonstanzConstanceGermany

Personalised recommendations