Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 172, Issue 11, pp 3059–3080 | Cite as

Would this paper exist if I hadn’t written it?

  • Samuel LebensEmail author
Article

Abstract

This paper wants to know whether it would exist, or could exist, in worlds in which I didn't write it. Before we can answer this question, we first of all have to inquire as to what, exactly, this paper is. After exploring two forms of Platonism (pure and impure), and a theory that defines literary works in terms of events, I shall argue that the term ‘this paper’ is actually infected with ambiguity. Does this paper need me? It depends upon what you mean by ‘this paper’. I lay out the options for what you might mean, and answer the question for each of the options.

Keywords

Ontology Art Literature 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Carl Mosser, Phil Swenson, Evan Fales, Ross Inman, Natalja Deng, Dustin Crummett, Robin Dembroff, Jeff Speaks, Tzvi Novick, Curtis Franks, and Gaby Lebens for very helpful conversations about these topics, and to all of the other people I’ve harangued about the nature of literary works. Thanks also to the anonymous reviewers who have helped me to improve this paper immeasurably. Any remaining faults in this paper, are mine alone—More accurately, I take responsibility for the possible referents of ‘this paper’ that anybody actually authored!

References

  1. Caplan, B., & Matheson, C. (2004). Can a musical work be created? British Journal of Aestehtics, 44(2), 113–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Cleland, C. (1991). On the individuation of events. Synthese, 86, 229–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Currie, G. (1989). An ontology of art. New York: St Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
  4. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  5. Davies, D. (2004). Art as performance. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dilworth, J. (2005). Review of David Davies, Art as performance. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 63(1), 77–80.Google Scholar
  7. Dodd, J. (2000). Musical works as eternal types. British Journal of Aesthetics, 40(4), 424–440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dodd, J. (2002). Defending musical platonism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 42(4), 380–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of world making. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  10. Goodman, J. (2004). A defense of creationism in fiction. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 67, 131–155.Google Scholar
  11. Goodman, N., & Elgin, C. (1988). Reconceptions in philosophy and other arts and sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  12. Irvin, S. (2014). Review of art and art-attempts. Notre Dame Review of Books. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/46001-art-and-art-attempts/
  13. Kania, A. (2005). Review of David Davies, Art as performance. Mind, 114(453), 137–141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Kim, J. (1976). Events as property exemplifications. In M. Brand & D. Walton (Eds.), Action theory. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  15. Kivy, P. (1983). Platonism in music: A kind of defence. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 19, 109–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lebens, S. (2010). On judgement: A multiple relation. PhD Thesis. Birkbeck College, London.Google Scholar
  17. Lessing, A. (1995). What is wrong with a forgery? In A. Neil & A. Ridley (Eds.), Arguing about art. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  18. Levinson, J. (1990). Music, art and metaphysics. Ithica and London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  20. Mag Uidhir, C. (2013). Art and art-attempts. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Pierce, C. S. (1906). Prolegomena to an apology for pragmatism. The Monist, 16(4), 492–546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Rohrbaugh, G. (2005). I could have done that. British Journal of Aesthetics, 45(1), 209–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Searle, J. (1975). The logical status of fictional discourse. New Literary History, 6, 319–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Stecker, R. (2005). Review of David Davies, Art as performance. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 63(1), 75–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Thomasson, A. (1999). Fiction and metaphysics. Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar
  26. Thomasson, A. (2003). Fictional characters and literary practices. British Journal of Aesthetics, 43(2), 138–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Thomasson, A. (2004). The ontology of art. In P. Kivy (Ed.), Blackwell guide to aesthetics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  28. Thomasson, A. (2008). Existence questions. Philosophical Studies, 141, 63–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. van Inwagen, P. (1977). Creatures of fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24, 299–308.Google Scholar
  30. Williams, B. (1970). The self and the future. Philosophical Review, 79(2), 161–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Wollheim, R. (1980). Art and its objects (2nd ed.). Cambridge: CUP.Google Scholar
  32. Wolterstorff, N. (1980). Works and worlds of art. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  33. Wolterstorff, N. (1991). Review of An ontology of art. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 49(1), 75–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Yagisawa, T. (1999). Against creationism in fiction. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 153–172.Google Scholar
  35. Ziff, P. (1972). What is said. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Center for Philosophy of ReligionRutgers UniversityNew BrunswickUSA

Personalised recommendations