Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 172, Issue 3, pp 653–669 | Cite as

An explication of emergence

  • Elanor Taylor
Article

Abstract

Philosophical debates about emergence are often marred by equivocation and lack of common ground, and dialogue about emergence between scientists and philosophers can be equally difficult. In this paper I offer a unified explication of emergence and argue that this explication can cut through much of the confusion evident in discussions of emergence. I defend an explication of the concept of emergence as the unavailability of a certain kind of scientific explanation for an observer or observers.

Keywords

Emergence Explanation Levels 

References

  1. Assad, A., & Packard, N. (1992). “Emergence”. In M.A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence (2008). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  2. Balazs, A., & Epstein, I. (2009). Emergent or just complex? Science, 325(5948), 1632–1634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Barnes, E. (2013). Emergence and fundamentality. Mind, 121, 873–901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bedau, M. (2003). “Downward causation and autonomy in weak emergence”. In M.A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence (2008). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bedau, M. (2008). Is weak emergence just in the mind? Minds and Machines, 18, 443–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bedau, M. A., & Humphreys, P. (Eds.) (2008). Emergence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  7. Block, N., & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review, 108(1), 1–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Broad, C. D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  10. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Chalmers, D. (2006). Strong and weak emergence. In P. Davies & P. Clayton (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Chalmers, D., & Jackson, F. (2002). Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review, 110, 315–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Connor, T. (2006). Emergent properties. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  14. Crane, T. (2001). The significance of emergence. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Dennett, D. (1991). Real Patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hempel, C., & Oppenheim, P. (1965). On the idea of emergence. In M.A. Bedau & P. Humphreys (Eds.), Emergence (2008). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. Kim, J. (2006). Emergence: Core ideas and issues. Synthese, 151(3), 547–559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Langton, C. (1995). Artificial life: An overview. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. McLaughlin, B. (1992). The rise and fall of British emergentism. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction?: Prospects for nonreductive physicalism. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  21. Morrison, M. (2012). Emergent physics and micro-ontology. Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 141–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Nitschke, J. (2009). Systems chemistry: Molecular networks come of age. Nature, 462, 736–738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Redhead, M. (1995). From physics to metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Silberstein, D., & McGeever, M. (1999). The search for ontological emergence. Philosophical Quarterly, 50(195), 182–200.Google Scholar
  25. Stephan, A. (2006). The dual role of emergence in philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Synthese, 151(3), 485–498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Teller, A. (1986). Relational holism and quantum mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37(1), 71–81.Google Scholar
  27. Wilson, J. (2005). Supervenience-based formulations of physicalism. Nous, 29, 426–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Wilson, J. (2010). Non-reductive physicalism and degrees of freedom. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 279–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Wilson, J. (2013). Metaphysical emergence: Weak and strong. In S. Mumford & M. Tugby (Eds.), Metaphysics and science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy and Religious StudiesIowa State UniversityAmesUSA

Personalised recommendations