Philosophical Studies

, Volume 164, Issue 3, pp 767–789 | Cite as

Pleonastic possible worlds

Article

Abstract

The role of possible worlds in philosophy is hard to overestimate. Nevertheless, their nature and existence is very controversial. This is particularly serious, since their standard applications depend on there being sufficiently many of them. The paper develops an account of possible worlds on which it is particularly easy to believe in their existence: an account of possible worlds as pleonastic entities. Pleonastic entities are entities whose existence can be validly inferred from statements that neither refer to nor quantify over them as a matter of conceptual necessity. Definitions are proposed that ensure that this is the case for possible worlds.

Keywords

Modality Possible worlds, account of Pleonastic entities Schiffer, Stephen 

References

  1. Adams, R. M. (1974). Theories of actuality. Noûs, 8, 211–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Barwise, J. (1981). Scenes and other situations. The Journal of Philosophy, 78, 369–397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Berkovski, S. (2011). Possible worlds: A Neo-Fregean alternative. Axiomathes, 21, 531–551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Crossley, J. N., & Humberstone, L. (1977). The logic of ‘actually’. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 8, 11–29.Google Scholar
  6. Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2000). Implicit definition and the a priori. In P. Boghossian & C. Peacocke (Eds.), New essays on the a priori (pp. 286–319). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2001). The reason’s proper study. Essays towards a Neo-Fregean philosophy of mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  8. Hughes, G. E., & Cresswell, M. J. (1996). A new introduction to modal logic. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Hugly, P., & Sayward, C. (1996). Intensionality and truth: An essay on the philosophy of A.N. Prior. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Humberstone, L. (1981). From worlds to possibilities. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10, 313–339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kratzer, A. (2010). Situations in natural language semantics. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/situations-semantics.
  12. Kripke, S. A. (1963). Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 83–94. (Reprinted in Reference and modality, pp. 63–72, by L. Linsky, Ed., 1971, London, Oxford University Press, Page references are to the reprint.)Google Scholar
  13. Kripke, S. A. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Künne, W. (2006). Properties in Abundance. In: P. F. Strawson, & Chakrabarti, A. (Eds.), Universals, concepts and qualities: New essays on the meaning of predicates (pp. 184–249). Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  15. Künne, W. (2007). Abstrakte Gegenstände. Semantik und Ontologie (2nd ed.). Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.Google Scholar
  16. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  17. Linsky, B., & Zalta, E. N. (1994). In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 431–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  19. Plantinga, A. (1976). Actualism and possible worlds. Theoria, 42, 139–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Plantinga, A. (1983). On existentialism. Philosophical Studies, 44, 1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Plantinga, A. (1985). Self-profile. In: J. E. Tomberlin, P. van Inwagen (Eds.), Alvin Plantinga (pp. 3–97). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  22. Rayo, A., & Yablo, S. (2001). Nominalism through de-nominalization. Noûs, 35, 74–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Schnieder, B. (2004). Substanzen und (ihre) Eigenschaften. Eine Studie zur analytischen Ontologie. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  25. Schnieder, B. (2005). Property designators, predicates, and rigidity. Philosophical Studies, 122, 227–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Schnieder, B. (2006). Canonical property designators. American Philosophical Quarterly, 43, 119–132.Google Scholar
  27. Stalnaker, R. C. (2003). Possible worlds. In Ways a world might be (pp. 25–39). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  28. Stalnaker, R. C. (2010). Merely possible propositions. In: B. Hale, & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality. Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 21–32). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Suppes, P. (1972). Axiomatic Set Theory (2nd ed.). New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  30. van Inwagen, P. (1986). Two concepts of possible worlds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9, 185–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Williamson, T. (1999). Truthmakers and the converse Barcan formula. Dialectica, 53, 253–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Williamson, T. (2002). Necessary existents. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Logic, thought and language (pp. 233–251). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Williamson, T. (forthcoming). Barcan formulas in second-order modal logic. In M. Frauchiger & W. K. Essler (Eds.), Themes from Barcan Marcus, Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag. http://www.philosophy.ox.ac.uk/__data/assets/pdf_file/0011/9479/Bernepaper.pdf.
  34. Yablo, S. (2000). Apriority and existence. In P. Boghossian & C. Peacocke (Eds.), New essays on the a priori (pp. 197–228). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Universität HamburgHamburgGermany

Personalised recommendations