Philosophical Studies

, Volume 162, Issue 2, pp 275–290 | Cite as

Descriptions, ambiguity, and representationalist theories of interpretation

Article
  • 206 Downloads

Abstract

Theories of descriptions tend to involve commitments about the ambiguity of descriptions. For example, sentences containing descriptions are widely taken to be ambiguous between de re, de dicto, and intermediate interpretations and are sometimes thought to be ambiguous between the former and directly referential interpretations. I provide arguments to suggest that none of these interpretations are due to ambiguities (or indexicality). On the other hand, I argue that descriptions are ambiguous between the above family of interpretations and what may be called ‘institutional’ as well as generic interpretations. My arguments suggest that an adequate theory of descriptions may require considerable rethinking. Most contemporary theories of descriptions appear to be committed to one or more claims about the ambiguity of descriptions that I reject in this paper. I suggest that my observations provide a reason to renew efforts to develop a theory of descriptions within a representationalist theory of interpretation.

Keywords

Descriptions Ambiguity Generics Uniqueness Presupposition Representationalist Theories of Interpretation 

References

  1. Amaral, F. S. (2008). Definite descriptions are ambiguous. Analysis, 68(4), 288–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Atlas, J. (1977). Negation, ambiguity, and presupposition. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1, 323–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Atlas, J. (2005). Logic, meaning, and conversation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bach, K. (2004). Descriptions: Points of reference. In A. Bezuidenhout & M. Reimer (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bealer, G. (1993). A solution to Frege’s Puzzle. Philosophical perspectives, 7, Language and logic, pp. 17–59.Google Scholar
  6. Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Devitt, M. (2004). The case for referential descriptions. In A. Bezuidenhout & M. Reimer (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Devitt, M. (2007). Referential descriptions and conversational implicatures. EUJAP, 3(2), 7–32.Google Scholar
  9. Donnellan, K. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Elbourne, P. (2005). Situations and individuals. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Fiengo, R., & May, R. (1994). Indices and identity. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  12. Fodor, J. (1970). The linguistic description of opaque contexts. PhD thesis, MIT.Google Scholar
  13. Fox, D. (1999). Focus, parallelism, and accommodation. In T. Matthews & D. Strolovitch (Eds.), Proceedings of the ninth conference on semantics and linguistic theory (pp. 70–90). Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  14. Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In J. Kimball (Ed.), Syntax and semantics (Vol. 3, pp. 139–151). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  15. Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.Google Scholar
  16. Heim, I. (1990). E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13, 137–178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hintikka, K. J. J. (1973). Grammar and logic: Some borderline problems. In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language: Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford workshop on grammar and semantics (pp. 197–214). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  18. Ioup, G. (1975). Some universals for quantifier scope. Syntax and Semantics, 4, 37–58.Google Scholar
  19. Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic interpretation. In J. Groenendijk, et al. (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of natural language. Amsterdam: Matematisch Centrum.Google Scholar
  20. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog & J. Perry (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Karttunen, L. (1968). What makes definite noun phrases definite? RAND Corporation report P-3871.Google Scholar
  22. Karttunen, L. (1976). Discourse referents. In J. D. McCawley (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 7: Notes from the linguistic underground (pp. 363–385). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  23. Keshet, E. (2008). Good intensions: paving two roads to a theory of the De Re/De Dicto distinction. PhD thesis, MIT.Google Scholar
  24. Keshet, E. (forthcoming). Split intensionality: A new scope theory of de re and de dicto.Google Scholar
  25. Kripke, S. (1977). Speaker reference and semantic reference. In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language (pp. 6–27). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  26. Ludlow, P., & Segal, G. (2004). On a unitary semantical analysis for definite and indefinite descriptions. In A. Bezuidenhout & M. Reimer (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond: An interdisciplinary collection of essays on definite and indefinite descriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Merchant, J. (2008). An asymmetry in voice mismatches in VP-ellipsis and pseudo-gapping. Linguistic Inquiry, 39.1, 169–179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Moffett, M. (2003). Knowing facts and believing propositions: A solution to the problem of doxastic shift. Philosophical Studies, 115, 81–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 56(5), 177–187.Google Scholar
  31. Reimer, M. (1998). Donnellan’s distinction/Kripke’s test. Analysis, 58, 89–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Salmon, N. (2004). The good, the bad, and the ugly. In A. Bezuidenhout & M. Reimer (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 230–260). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Sennett, A. (2002). An ambiguity test for definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies, 111, 81–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Sharvy, R. (1980). A more general theory of definite descriptions. The Philosophical Review, 89, 607–623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Szabó, Z. G. (2000). Descriptions and uniqueness. Philosophical Studies, 101, 29–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Zwicky, A. M., & Sadock, J. M. (1975). Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In J. P. Kimball (Ed.), Syntax and semantics (Vol. 4, pp. 1–36). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentPrinceton UniversityPrincetonUSA

Personalised recommendations