Skip to main content
Log in

Simulation and the first-person

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article focuses on, and critiques, Goldman’s view that third-person mind-reading is grounded in first-person introspection. It argues, on the contrary, that first-person awareness of propositional attitude events is always interpretative, resulting from us turning our mind-reading abilities upon ourselves.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Baars, B. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. (1997). In the theatre of consciousness. NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Science, 6, 47–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. (2003). How brain reveals mind: Neuroimaging supports the central role of conscious experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, 100–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B., Ramsoy, T., & Laureys, S. (2003). Brain, consciousness, and the observing self. Trends in Neurosciences, 26, 671–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosco, F., Friedman, O., & Leslie, A. (2006). Recognition of pretend and real actions in play by 1- and 2-year-olds: Early success and why they fail. Cognitive Development, 21, 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Botterill, G., & Carruthers, P. (1999). The philosophy of psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brasil-Neto, J., Pascual-Leone, A., Valls-Solé, J., Cohen, L., & Hallett, M. (1992). Focal transcranial magnetic stimulation and response bias in a forced choice task. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 55, 964–966.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briñol, P., & Petty, R. (2003). Overt head movements and persuasion: a self-validation analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 1123–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, R., & Whiten, A. (Eds.). (1988). Machiavellian intelligence: Social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes, and humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, R., & Whiten, A. (Eds.). (1997). Machiavellian intelligence II: Extensions and evaluations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind: Massive modularity and the flexibility of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2008). Cartesian epistemology: Is the theory of the self-transparent mind innate? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15, 28–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (forthcoming). Introspection: Divided and partly eliminated. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition, 79, 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., Cohen, L., Bihan, D., Mangin, J., Poline, J., et al. (2001). Cerebral mechanisms of word priming and unconscious repetition masking. Nature Neuroscience, 4, 752–758.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Sergent, C., & Changeux, J. (2003). A neuronal network model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data during conscious perception. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 100, 8520–8525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, R. (2000). On the origin of the human mind. In P. Carruthers & A. Chamberlain (Eds.), Evolution and the human mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagly, A., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, G. (1965). Post-hypnotic amnesia and post-hypnotic effect. British Journal of Psychiatry, 111, 316–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, U., & Happé, F. (1999). Theory of mind and self-consciousness: What is it like to be autistic? Mind and Language, 14, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. (1995). Consciousness and the cerebral hemispheres. In M. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences. Cambrigdge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1994). Minds, bodies, and persons: Young children’s understanding of the self and others as reflected in imitation and theory of mind research. In S. Parker, R. Mitchell, & M. Boccia (Eds.), Self-awareness in animals and humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Slaughter, V. (1991). Young children’s understanding of changes in their mental states. Child Development, 62, 98–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurlburt, R., Happé, F., & Frith, U. (1994). Sampling the form of inner experience in three adults with Asperger syndrome. Psychological Medicine, 24, 385–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kazak, S., Collis, G., & Lewis, V. (1997). Can young people with autism refer to knowledge states? Evidence from their understanding of “know” and “guess”. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 38, 1001–1009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreiman, G., Fried, I., & Koch, C. (2003). Single neuron correlates of subjective vision in the human medial temporal lobe. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 99, 8378–8383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-olds understand false beliefs? Science, 5719, 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K., Baillargeon, R., & Leslie, A. (2007). 15-month-old infants detect violations in pretend scenarios. Acta Psychologica, 124, 106–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, W., Baron-Cohen, S., & Rutter, M. (1998). Understanding intention in normal development and in autism. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 16, 337–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, C., Schwebel, D., & Singer, J. (1997). Preschoolers’ attributions of mental states in pretense. Child Development , 68, 1133–1142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J., & Hill, E. (2001). Action-monitoring and intention reporting in children with autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 42, 317–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B., & Leslie, A. (1999). Modularity, development, and “theory of mind”. Mind and Language, 14, 131–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheehan, P., & Orne, M. (1968). Some comments on the nature of post-hypnotic behavior. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 146, 209–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., Senju, A., & Csibra, G. (2007). Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by 2-year-olds. Psychological Science, 18, 587–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surian, L., Caldi, S., & Sperber, D. (2007). Attribution of beliefs by 13-month old infants. Psychological Science, 18, 580–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D., & Wheatley, T. (1999). Apparent mental causation: Sources of the experience of the will. American Psychologist, 54, 480–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. (1990). The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. (2002). Strangers to ourselves. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., Hogrefe, G., & Perner, J. (1988). Children’s understanding of informational access as a source of knowledge. Child Development, 59, 386–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Carruthers.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Carruthers, P. Simulation and the first-person. Philos Stud 144, 467–475 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9357-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9357-y

Keywords

Navigation