Skip to main content
Log in

In defense of reliabilism

  • Original paper
  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Objections to reliabilist theories of knowledge and justification have looked insuperable. Reliability is a property of the process of belief formation. But the generality problem apparently makes the specification of any such process ambiguous. The externalism of reliability theories clashes with strongly internalist intuitions. The reliability property does not appear closed under truth-preserving inference, whereas closure principles have strong intuitive appeal. And epistemic paradoxes, like the preface and the lottery, seem unavoidable if knowledge or justification depends on the frequency with which a process generates true beliefs. The present theory has the conceptual resources to meet these challenges. It requires that a justificatory belief-formation process be intentionally applied. It distinguishes the justification of beliefs from that of the believer. And it avoids a frequency interpretation of reliability by introducing a notion of the normalcy of conditions under which processes are intentionally used.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, truth, and knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonjour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed), Philosophical perspectives, vol. 13, supp. to NOÛS (pp. 57–91). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. S. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp.␣1–23) Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Heller, M. (1989). Relevant alternatives. Philosophical Studies, 55, 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1999). The proper role for contextualism in an anti-luck epistemology. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives vol. 13, supp. to NOÛS (pp. 115–131). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Leplin, J. (2004). A theory’s predictive success can warrant belief in the unobservable entities it postulates. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science (pp. 117–133). Malden MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Long, D. (1992). The self-defeating character of skepticism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 67–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2002). “Radical skepticism, epistemological externalism, and closure. Theoria, 66, 129–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1985). The coherence of virtue and the virtue of coherence. Synthèse, 64, 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jarrett Leplin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Leplin, J. In defense of reliabilism. Philos Stud 134, 31–42 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9018-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9018-3

Keywords

Navigation