Skip to main content
Log in

Reasons and psychological causes

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The causal theory of reasons holds that acting for a reason entails that the agent’s action was caused by his or her beliefs and desires. While Donald Davidson (1963) and others effectively silenced the first objections to the theory, a new round has emerged. The most important recent attack is presented by Jonathan Dancy in Practical Reality (2000) and subsequent work. This paper will defend the causal theory against Dancy and others, including Schueler (1995), Stoutland (1999, 2001), and Ginet (2002).

Dancy observes that our reasons are neither psychological states nor causes, and that our reasons can be both motivating and normative. I argue that these observations are fully compatible with the causal theory. According to the reductive version I develop for both cognitive and optative reasons, what it is for an action to be done for a reason is for certain beliefs and desires to cause the action in a particular way. Our reasons for action are the objects of some of those beliefs and desires. The causal process has two stages. This theory explains not only Dancy’s observations, but also many other facts about reasons that alternative theories leave unexplained. I argue against Schueler and others that the non-appetitive desires entailed by acting for reasons are no less distinct and independent causal factors than the beliefs entailed. I go on to rebut arguments that the relation between psychological states and actions cannot be causal because it is non-empirical, rational, normative, or non-deterministic, and that explanations in terms of psychological causes are incompatible with explanations in terms of reasons.

I make no claim here about the precise adequacy of the theoretical definitions I present. My goal is to show that a systematic theory along these lines is the most promising and fruitful approach to understanding an important aspect of human nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Alston, W.P. (1967d): ‘Wants, Actions, and Causal Explanations’, in H.N. Castaneda (ed.), Minds, Intentionality, and Perception (pp. 301–341), Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. (1957): Intention, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. (1973): Belief, Truth, and Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1971): ‘Intentionalistic Explanations of Action’, Metaphilosophy 2, 241–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1982): ‘A Theory of Practical Reasoning’, American Philosophical Quarterly 19, 25–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1986a): ‘Intending, Intentional Action, and Desire’, in J. Marks (ed.), The Ways of Desire (pp. 17–38), Precedent Press.

  • Audi, R. (1986b): ‘Acting for Reasons’, Philosophical Review 95, 511–546.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1995): ‘Practical Tortoise Raising’, Mind 104, 695–711.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R.B. and Kim, J. (1963): ‘Wants as Explanations of Actions’, Journal of Philosophy 60, 425–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (1997): ‘Reasons and Motivation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 71(Suppl.), 131–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R.M. (1964): ‘The Descriptive Element in the Concept of Action’, Journal of Philosophy 61, 613–625.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2002): ‘Libertarian Views: Critical Survey of Noncausal and Event-Causal Accounts of Free Agency’, in R. Kane (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (pp. 356–385), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (1994-1995): ‘Why There Is Really No Such Thing as the Theory of Motivation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2000): Practical Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (forthcoming): ‘Precís’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Dancy, J. (forthcoming): ‘Replies’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Dancy, J. (forthcoming): ‘Two Ways of Explaining Actions’, in J. Hyman and H. Steward (eds.), Action and Agency, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Darwall, S. (forthcoming): ‘Desires, Reasons, and Causes’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Darwall, S. (2001): ‘Because I Want It’, Social Philosophy and Policy 18, 129–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963): ‘Actions, Reasons, and Causes’, Journal of Philosophy 60, 685–700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W.A. (1977): ‘Reasons’, in A Systematization of Commonsense Psychology (pp. 344–403), Ph.D. Dissertation, Princeton University.

  • Davis, W.A. (1984b): ‘The Two Senses of Desire’, Philosophical Studies 45, 181–195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W.A. (2003): Meaning, Expression, and Thought, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W.A. (forthcoming): ‘Psychologism and Humeanism’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Donnellan, K. (1967): ‘Reasons and Causes’, in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy (pp. 85–88), New York: Macmillan Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1989): ‘Reasons and Causes’, Philosophical Perspectives 3, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, W.D. (1963): ‘Action-Guiding Reasons’, Journal of Philosophy 60, 703–718.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. (ed.) (1988): Probability and Causality: Essays in Honor of Wesley C. Salmon, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1972): ‘Reasons for Actions and Desires’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 46(Suppl.), 203–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1963): Practical Reasoning, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1989): ‘Reasons Explanations of Action: An Incompatibilist account’, Philosophical Perspectives 3, 17–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (2002): ‘Reasons Explanations of Action: Causalist versus Noncausalist Accounts’, in R. Kane (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (pp. 386–405), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1970): A Theory of Human Action, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. (1961): ‘The Causal Theory of Perception’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 35(Suppl.), 121–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gustavson, D. (1973): ‘A Critical Survey of the Reasons vs. Causes Argument in Recent Philosophy of Action’, Metaphilosophy 4, 269–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (eds.) (1991): Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind, Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1993): ‘Agency and Causal Explanation’, in J. Heil and A. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation (1995) (pp. 161–185), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (2002): ‘Some Neglected Paths in the Free Will Labyrinth’, in R. Kane (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will (pp. 407–437), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1966): ‘An Argument for the Identity Theory’, Journal of Philosohpy 63, 17–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, D. (1974): ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’, American Philosophical Quarterly 11, 169–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, D. (1982): ‘Beliefs, Desires and Reasons for Actions’, American Philosophical Quarterly 19, 241–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, C. and Macdonald, G. (eds.) (1995): Connectionism: Debates in Psychological Explanation, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marks, J. (1986): ‘The Difference between Motivation and Desire’, in J. Marks (ed.), The Ways of Desire (pp. 133–147), Chicago: Precedent Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1978): ‘Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 52(Suppl.), 13–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • McFetridge, I.G. (1978): ‘Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 52(Suppl.), 31–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1979): ‘Action and Its Explanation’, in N. Bolton (ed.), Philosophical Problems in Psychology (pp. 20–42). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • McQueen, D. (1973): ‘Belief and Reasons for Belief’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 47, 69–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melden, A.I. (1961): Free Action, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1989): ‘Motivational Internalism: The Powers and Limits of Practical Reasoning’, Philosophia 19, 417–436

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. and Moser, P. (1994): ‘Intentional Action’, Noûs 28, 39–68. Reprinted in A. Mele (ed.) 1997: The Philosophy of Action (pp. 223-255), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1970): The Possibility of Altruism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1997): ‘Reasons and Motivation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 71(Suppl.), 99–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R.S. (1958): The Concept of Motivation, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. and Smith, M. (1990): ‘Backgrounding Desire’, Philosophical Review 99, 565–592.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1971): ‘Reasons for Action’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1, 173–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D.E. and McClelland, J.L. (1986): Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schueler, G.F. (1995): Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwayder, D.S. (1965): The Stratification of Behavior, New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1987): ‘The Humean Theory of Motivation’, Mind 96, 36–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1995): ‘Internal Reasons’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55, 109–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoutland, F. (1970): ‘The Logical Connection Argument’, in N. Rescher (ed.), Studies in the Theory of Knowledge (pp. 117–129), Oxford: Oxford University Press. American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series No. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoutland, F. (1999): ‘Intentionalists and Davidson on Rational Explanation’, in G. Meggle (ed.), Actions, Norms, Values (pp. 191–208), Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoutland, F. (2001): ‘Responsive Action and the Belief-Desire Model’, Grazer-Philosophische-Studien 61, 83–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, R. (1960): ‘I Can’, Philosophical Review 69.

  • Taylor, R. (1966): Action and Purpose, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright, G.H. (1971): Explanation and Understanding, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R.J. (1990): ‘How to Argue about Practical Reason’, Mind 99, 355–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R.J. (1999): ‘Introduction’, in R.J. Wallace (ed.), Reason, Emotion, and Will (pp. xi–xxiv), Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1979): ‘Internal and External Reasons’, in R. Harrison (ed.), Rational Action, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1989): ‘Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame’, Logos 10, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Davis, W.A. Reasons and psychological causes. Philos Stud 122, 51–101 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-7249-3

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-7249-3

Keywords

Navigation