Advertisement

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 17, Issue 1, pp 131–156 | Cite as

Enactivism, second-person engagement and personal responsibility

  • Janna van GrunsvenEmail author
Article

Abstract

Over the course of the past few decades 4E approaches that theorize cognition and agency as embodied, embedded, extended, and/or enactive have garnered growing support from figures working in philosophy of mind and cognitive science (Cf. Chemero 2009; Dreyfus 2005; Gallagher 2005; Haugeland 1998; Hurley 1998; Noë 2004; Thompson 2007; Varela et al. 1991). Correspondingly, there has been a rising interest in the wider conceptual and practical implications of 4E views. Several proposals have for instance been made regarding 4E’s bearing on ethical theory (Cf. Colombetti and Torrance, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 505–526, 2009; Cash, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 645–671 2010). In this paper I contribute to this trend by critically examining the enactive contribution made by Colombetti and Torrance, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 505–526 (2009) and by laying the foundations for an alternative enactive approach. Building off recent enactive approaches to social interaction, Colombetti and Torrance, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), (2009, 518) maintain that many of our actions and intentions “and in particular the ethical significance of what we do and mean” are “emergent from the interactions in which we participate”. Taking this seriously, they argue, entails a radical shift away from moral theory’s traditional emphasis on individual or personal responsibility. I challenge their suggestion that accepting a broadly enactive 4E approach to cognition and agency entails the kind of wholesale shift they propose. To make my case I start by revisiting some of the general theoretical commitments characteristic of enactivism, including some relevant insights that can be gathered from Vasudevi Reddy’s broadly enactive approach to developmental psychology. After that I examine both the arguments internal to Colombetti and Torrance’s proposal and, in an effort to sketch the beginnings of an alternative view, I draw some connections between enactivism, the ethics of care and P.F. Strawson’s work on personal responsibility. I believe that a consideration of the commonalities but also the differences between these views helps advance the important conversation concerning the link between enactivism and questions of personal responsibility in ethical theory that Colombetti and Torrance have undeniably helped jumpstart.

Keywords

Enactivism Second-person engagement Social interaction Participatory sensemaking Personal responsibility Ethics of care P.F. Strawson 

References

  1. Ayer, A.J. (1954). Freedom and Necessity. In Philosophical Essays. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1954.Google Scholar
  2. Benson, P. (2000). Self-worth and the social character of responsibility. In C. Mackenzie & N. Stoljar (Eds.), Relational autonomy: feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Cash, M. (2010). Extended cognition, personal responsibility, and relational autonomy. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 645–671.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Clark, A. (2003). Natural born cyborgs: minds, technologies and the future of human intelligence. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Colombetti, G., & Torrance, S. (2009). Emotion and ethics: An inter-(en) active approach. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 505–526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 33–88). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Dreyfus, H. L. (2005). Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday expertise. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 79 (2):47–65.Google Scholar
  10. Dreyfus, H.L. (2009). The Myth of the Pervasiveness of the Mental, unpublished keynote talk at The Phenomenological Body – Its Spaces and Limits, graduate student conference at the New School for Social Research (March 2009).Google Scholar
  11. Froese, T., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2009). Sociality and the life–mind continuity thesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 439–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4). doi: 10.1007/s11097-009-9136-4.
  13. Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Gallagher, S. (2007). Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience, 2(3–4), 353–365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
  16. Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind Embodied and Embedded. In Having thought: essays in the metaphysics of mind. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Held, V. (2006). The ethics of care: Personal, political, and global. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Jonas, H. (1996). Evolution and freedom: on the continuity among life-forms. In Mortality and morality: a search for the good after Auschwitz. Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Kittay, E. (2009). The personal is philosophical is political. A philosopher and mother of a cognitively disabled person sends notes from the battle ground. Metaphilosophy, 40(3–4), 606–627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Noë, A. (2010). Out of our heads: Why you are not your brain, and other lessons from the biology of consciousness. New York: Hill and Wang.Google Scholar
  23. Perrin, T., & May, H. (2000). Wellbeing in dementia: An occupational approach for therapists and carers. Philadelphia, PA: Churchill Livingstone.Google Scholar
  24. Ratcliffe, M. (2007). Rethinking comonsense psychology: a critique of folk psychology, theory of mind and simulation. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Reddy, V. 2008. How infants know minds. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Strawson, P.F. (2008). Freedom and resentment. In M. McKenna & P. Russell (Eds.), Free will and reactive attitudes. Ashgate Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  27. Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Harvard (Belknap).Google Scholar
  28. Varela, F. (1991). Organism: a meshwork of selfless selves. In A. I. Tauber (Ed.), Organism and the origins of self. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Springer Science.Google Scholar
  29. Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Wiggins, D. (2003). Towards a reasonable libertarianism. Reprinted In G. Watson (Ed.), Free will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.TU DelftDelftThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations