Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 13, Issue 2, pp 257–274 | Cite as

Neural representationalism, the Hard Problem of Content and vitiated verdicts. A reply to Hutto & Myin (2013)

Article

Abstract

Colombo’s (Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2013) plea for neural representationalism is the focus of a recent contribution to Phenomenology and Cognitive Science by Daniel D. Hutto and Erik Myin. In that paper, Hutto and Myin have tried to show that my arguments fail badly. Here, I want to respond to their critique clarifying the type of neural representationalism put forward in my (Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2013) piece, and to take the opportunity to make a few remarks of general interest concerning what Hutto and Myin have dubbed “the Hard Problem of Content.”

Keywords

Neural representationalism Hard problem of content Un-metaphysical cognitive science 

References

  1. Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society: The nature and dynamics of social norms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bicchieri, C. & Muldoon, R. (2011). Social Norms, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/social-norms/
  3. Bokulich, A. (2008). Reexamining the quantum‐classical relation: Beyond reductionism and pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bokulich, A. (2012). Distinguishing explanatory from Non-explanatory fictions. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 725–737.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (Vol. I, pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  6. Carnap, R. (1974). An introduction to the philosophy of science. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  7. Chemero, A. (2000). Anti-representationalism and the dynamical stance. Philosophy of Science, 67, 625–647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Science, 36, 181–253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101, 401–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Colombo, M. (2013). Explaining social norm compliance. A plea for neural representations. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences online first 2013. doi:10.1007/s11097-013-9296-0.
  11. Colombo, M. (2014). Two neurocomputational building blocks of social norm compliance. Biology and Philosophy, 29(1), 71–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Colombo, M., Hartmann, S., & van Iersel, R. (2014). Models, Mechanisms, and Coherence. The British Journal for Philosophy of Science (in press).Google Scholar
  13. Crane, T. (2003). The mechanical mind (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  14. Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Dayan, P. (2008). The role of value systems in decision making. In C. Engel & W. Singer (Eds.), Better than conscious? decision making, the human mind, and implications for institutions (pp. 51–57). Frankfurt: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. de Charms, R. C., & Zador, A. (2000). Neural representation and the cortical code. Annual Review Neuroscience, 23, 613–647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dowe, P. (2008). Causal Processes. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL= http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/causation-process/
  18. Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Fodor, J. (1996). Deconstructing Dennett’s Darwin. Mind and Language, 11, 246–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Frigg, R. (2010). Fiction in Science. In J. Woods (Ed.), Fictions and models: New essays (pp. 247–287). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.Google Scholar
  21. Friston, K. J. (2005). A theory of cortical responses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 360, 815–836.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Haugeland, J. (1991). Representational Genera. In W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 61–89). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  23. Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013a). Neural representations not needed - no more pleas, please. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-013-9331-1.Google Scholar
  24. Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013b). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: a mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 601–627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Kawato, M. (2008). From “Understanding the brain by creating the brain” towards manipulative neuroscience. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 363, 2201–2214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Knill, D. C., & Pouget, A. (2004). The Bayesian brain: the role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation. Trends in Neurosciences, 27, 712–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: the metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18(1), 27–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Nicolelis, M. A. L. (2001). Actions from thoughts. Nature, 409, 403–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Nicolelis, M. A., & Lebedev, M. A. (2009). Principles of neural ensemble physiology underlying the operation of brain-machine interfaces. Nature Review Neuroscience, 10, 530–540.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Persson, J. (2010). Activity-based accounts of mechanism and the threat of polygenic effects. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 135–149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Pouget, A., Dayan, P., & Zemel, R. S. (2003). Inference and computation with population codes. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 26, 381–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Psillos, S. (2004). A glimpse of the secret connexion: harmonizing mechanisms with counterfactuals. Perspectives on Science, 12(3), 288–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Rheinberger, H.J. and Müller-Wille, S. (2010). Gene. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/gene/
  38. Shea, N. (2012). Reward prediction error signals are meta-representational. Noûs. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2012.00863.x.Google Scholar
  39. Shea, N. (2013). Naturalising representational content. Philosophy Compass, 8(5), 496–509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, prediction and search (2nd ed.). Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  41. Sprevak, M. (2013). Fictionalism about neural representations. The Monist, 96, 539–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Tabery, J. (2004). Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Waters, K. (2013). Molecular Genetics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/molecular-genetics/
  44. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Woodward, J. (2008). Response to Strevens. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75, 193–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Woodward, J. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: its scope and limits. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 87(1), 39–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Tilburg Center for Logic, General Ethics, and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS)Tilburg UniversityTilburgThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations