Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 12, Issue 1, pp 27–40 | Cite as

On-line false belief understanding qua folk psychology?

Article

Abstract

In this paper, I address Mitchell Herschbach’s arguments against the phenomenological critics of folk psychology. Central to Herschbach’s arguments is the introduction of Michael Wheeler’s distinction between ‘on-line’ and ‘off-line’ intelligence to the debate on social understanding. Herschbach uses this distinction to describe two arguments made by the phenomenological critics. The first is that folk psychology is exclusively off-line and mentalistic. The second is that social understanding is on-line and non-mentalistic. To counter the phenomenological critics, Herschbach argues for the existence of on-line false belief understanding. This demonstrates that folk psychology is not restricted to off-line forms and that folk psychology is more widespread than the phenomenological critics acknowledge. In response, I argue the on-line/off-line distinction is a problematic way of demarcating the phenomenological critics from orthodox accounts of folk psychology.

Keywords

Folk psychology On-line/Off-line cognition Phenomenological critics Social understanding 

References

  1. Andrews, K. (2008). It’s in your nature: a pluralistic folk psychology. Synthese, 165(1), 13–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2002). A new false belief test for 36-month-olds. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 20, 393–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Carruthers, P. (2009). How we know our own minds: the relationship between mindreading and metacognition. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(2), 121–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Currie, G. (2008). Some ways of understanding people. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 211–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. De Jaegher, H. (2009a). What made me want the cheese? A reply to Shaun Gallagher and Dan Hutto. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(2), 549–550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. De Jaegher, H. (2009b). Social understanding through direct perception? Yes, by interacting. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(2), 535–542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5-7): 83–107. Google Scholar
  8. Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Gallagher, S. (2007). Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience, 2(3–4), 353–365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gallagher, S. (2009a). Deep and dynamic interaction: response to Hanne De Jaegher. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(2), 547–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gallagher, S. (2009b). Two problems of intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16(6–8), 289–308.Google Scholar
  12. Gallagher, S. (2012). In defense of phenomenological approaches to social cognition: Interacting with the critics. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(2):187–212.Google Scholar
  13. Herschbach, M. (2008a). Folk psychological and phenomenological accounts of social perception. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 223–235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Herschbach, M. (2008b). False belief understanding and the phenomenological critics of folk psychology. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(12), 33–56.Google Scholar
  15. Jacob, P. (2011). The direct perception model of empathy: a critique. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 519–540.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Keysar, B., Barr, D. J., Balin, J. A., & Brauner, J. S. (2000). Taking perspective in conversation: the role of mutual knowledge in comprehension. Psychological Science, 11(1), 32–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Keysar, B., Lin, S., & Barr, D. J. (2003). Limits on theory of mind use in adults. Cognition, 89(1), 25–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Low, J., & Wang, B. (2011). On the long road to mentalism in children’s spontaneous false belief understanding: are we there yet? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 411–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308(5719), 255–258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Ratcliffe, M. (2005). Folk psychology and the biological basis of intersubjectivity. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Philosophy, biology and life (pp. 211–233). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Ratcliffe, M. (2006). ‘Folk Psychology’ is not folk psychology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 5(1), 31–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Ratcliffe, M. (2007). From folk psychology to commonsense. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology reassessed (pp. 223–243). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Ratcliffe, M. (2009). There are no folk psychological narratives. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16(6–8), 379–406.Google Scholar
  24. Southgate, V., Senju, A., & Csibra, G. (2007). Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by two-year-olds. Psychological Science, 18(7), 587–592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Spaulding, S. (2010). Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind and Language, 25(1), 119–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: the next step. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  27. Zahavi, D., & Gallagher, S. (2008). The (in)visibility of others: a reply to Herschbach. Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 237–243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyDurham UniversityDurhamUK

Personalised recommendations