Abstract
As yet, there is no enactive account of social cognition. This paper extends the enactive concept of sense-making into the social domain. It takes as its departure point the process of interaction between individuals in a social encounter. It is a well-established finding that individuals can and generally do coordinate their movements and utterances in such situations. We argue that the interaction process can take on a form of autonomy. This allows us to reframe the problem of social cognition as that of how meaning is generated and transformed in the interplay between the unfolding interaction process and the individuals engaged in it. The notion of sense-making in this realm becomes participatory sense-making. The onus of social understanding thus moves away from strictly the individual only.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.Notes
We must acknowledge here that by autonomy of the interactors we should understand a possibly multi-dimensional complex of identities that co-exist in what we call a subject, from his physical body, his sensorimotor integration, his function in the interaction, to his broader contextual, relational and historical roles. Complex interactions may result in the loss of the autonomy associated with a specific identity but they are still social as long as other autonomous identities remain in interaction (e.g., a conversation where an employee loses his job is a definitive blow to the sustained identity of the employee as such, but not to the social agent that still enjoys his autonomy to express his reaction to the situation). We expect that even though the proposed distinction holds in general (encounters are not social if an interactor’s autonomy is lost), specific instances must be unpacked carefully in terms of what identities are at play in what we have loosely termed an interactor.
Participatory sense-making is not restricted to human social interactions. Many social animals build up coherences of significance by engaging in coordinated displays, such as circle-walking in wolves where potential contenders size each other up by making turns around each other (Moran et al. 1981), their intention to fight or not being affected by the emergent coordination. Even in simple models in evolutionary robotics the discrimination between different significant contexts can be performed through appropriate coordination between individuals (Di Paolo, Rohde and De Jaegher 2007; Quinn 2001). Recent work modelling the detection of social contingency in minimal agents shows in explicit terms how individual perception alters its meaning as a result of social coordination (Di Paolo, Rohde and Iizuka 2007).
References
Auvray, M., Lenay, C., & Stewart, J. (2006). The attribution of intentionality in a simulated environment: The case of minimalist devices. In Tenth Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness. Oxford, UK.
Boden, M. (2006). Of islands and interactions. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, 53–63.
Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Cambridge: Polity.
Buck, J., & Buck, E. (1976). Synchronous fireflies. Scientific American, 234, 74–85 (May).
Colombetti, G. (2007). Enactive appraisal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, (This issue).
Condon, W. S., & Ogston, W. D. (1971). Speech and body motion synchrony of the speaker–hearer. In D. L. Horton, & J. J. Jenkins (Eds.) The perception of language. Columbus, Ohio: Charles E. Merril Publishing Co.
Cook, J. E. (1991). Correlated activity in the CNS: A role on every timescale? Trends in Neurosciences, 14, 397–401.
Cowley, S. (2007). How human infants deal with symbol grounding. Interaction Studies, 8, 81–104.
Currie, G. (2007). Narrative frameworks. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.) Narrative and understanding persons: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60 (pp. 17–42). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
De Jaegher, H. (2006). Social interaction rhythm and participatory sense-making: An embodied, interactional approach to social understanding, with implications for autism, D.Phil. Thesis. In University of Sussex, Brighton, UK.
de Vignemont, F., & Singer, T. (2006). The empathic brain: How, when and why? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 435–441.
Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 97–125.
Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2007). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo, (Eds.), Enaction: towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & Iizuka, H. (2007). Sensitivity to social contingency or stability of interaction? Modelling the dynamics of perceptual crossing. New Ideas in Psychology.
Fogel, A. (1993). Developing through relationships: Origins of communication, self and culture. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology and cognitive science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4, 195–214.
Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 83–108.
Gallagher, S. (2004). Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction Theory as an alternative to Theory of Mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 11, 199–217.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. (2007). Logical and phenomenological arguments against simulation theory. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Minding our practice: Folk psychology re-assessed. Springer.
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., et al. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.
Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external events: A ‘who’ system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 465–477.
Gill, S. P., Kawamori, M., Katagiri, Y., et al. (2000). Role of Body Moves in dialogue. International Journal of Language and Communication, 12, 89–114.
Goffman, E. (1972). Interaction ritual: Essays on face-to-face behavior. London: Allen Lane.
Goffman, E. (1983). The interaction order. American Sociological Review, 48, 1–17.
Granic, I. (2000). The self-organization of parent-child relations: Beyond bidirectional models. In M. D. Lewis, & I. Granic (Eds.) Emotion, development, and self-organization. Dynamic systems approaches to emotional development (pp. 267–297). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haken, H., & Köpchen, H. P. (1991). Rhythms in physiological systems. Berlin: Springer.
Hobson, R. P. (2002). The cradle of thought. London: Macmillan.
Hutto, D. D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind and Language, 19, 548–573.
Hutto, D. D. (2007). The narrative practice hypothesis: Origins and applications of Folk Psychology. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement: Cambridge University Press.
Jaffe, J., Beebe, B., & Feldstein, S., et al. (2001). Rhythms of dialogue in infancy: Coordinated timing in development. Oxford: Blackwell.
Jaffe, J., & Feldstein, S. (1970). Rhythms of dialogue. London: Academic.
Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life. Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behaviour. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kendon, A. (1990). Conducting interaction: patterns of behavior in focused encounters. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Klin, A., Jones, W., Schultz, R., et al. (2003). The enactive mind, or from actions to cognition: Lessons from autism. Philosophical Transactions of The Royal Society London B, 358, 345–360.
Kuramoto, Y. (1984). Chemical oscillations, waves and turbulence. Berlin: Springer.
Moran, G., Fentress, J. C., & Golani, I. (1981). A description of relational patterns of movement during “ritualized fighting” in wolves. Animal Behavior, 29, 1146–1165.
Moreno, A., & Etxeberria, A. (2005). Agency in natural and artificial systems. Artificial Life, 11, 161–176.
Murray, L., & Trevarthen, C. (1985). Emotional regulation of interactions between 2-month-olds and their mothers. In T. M. Field, & N. A. Fox (Eds.) Social perception in infants (pp. 177–197). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Myin, E. (2003). An account of color without a subject? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 42–43.
Pickering, M. J., & Garrod, S. (2004). Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27,169–190.
Port, R. F., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.) (1995). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Quinn, M. (2001). Evolving communication without dedicated communication channels. In Advances in artificial life: Sixth European Conference on Artificial Life (ECAL 2001). Prague: Springer pp. 357–366.
Ratcliffe, M. (2007). Rethinking commonsense psychology: A critique of folk psychology, theory of mind and simulation. Hampshire/New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Ruhleder, K., & Jordan, B. (2001). Co-constructing non-mutual realities: Delay-generated trouble in distributed interaction. Journal of Computer Supported Cooperative Work, 10, 113–138.
Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation volumes I and II. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sacks, H., Schegloff, E. A., & Jefferson, G. (1974). A simplest systematics for the organization of turn-taking for conversation. Language, 50, 696–735.
Schiffrin, D. (1994). Approaches to discourse. Oxford: Blackwell.
Schmidt, R. C., & O'Brien, B. (1997). Evaluating the dynamics of unintended interpersonal coordination. Ecological Psychology, 9, 189–206.
Shanker, S., & King, B. J. (2002). The emergence of a new paradigm in ape language research. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 605–656.
Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999). Emotion and movement: A beginning empirical-phenomenological analysis of their relationship. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 259–277.
Stern, D. (2002/1977). The first relationship: Infant and mother. London: Harvard University Press.
Thompson, E. (2001). Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 1–32.
Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 407–427.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press.
Thompson, E., & Varela, F. J. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 418–425.
Thorpe, W. H. (1972). Duetting and antiphonal song in birds: Its extent and significance. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Torrance, S. (2005). In search of the enactive: Introduction to special issue on enactive experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 357–368.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before speech (pp. 321–347). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tronick, E. (2005). Why is connection with others so critical? The formation of dyadic states of consciousness and the expansion of individuals’ states of consciousness: Coherence governed selection and the co-creation of meaning out of messy meaning making. In J. Nadel, & D. Muir (Eds.) Emotional development (pp. 293–316). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tronick, E. Z., Als, H., & Adamson, L. (1979). Structure of early face-to-face communicative interactions. In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before speech (pp. 349–370). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
van Gelder, T. (1999). Wooden iron? Husserlian phenomenology meets cognitive science. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 245–265). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier (North Holland).
Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. Tauber (Ed.) Organism and the origin of self pp. 79–107. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, 330–349.
Varela, F. J. (1997). Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition, 34, 72–87.
Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 266–314). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.
Winfree, A. T. (2001). The geometry of biological time. London: Springer.
Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank Stephen Cowley, Marek McGann and Steve Torrance for their very helpful comments on this paper.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E. Participatory sense-making. Phenom Cogn Sci 6, 485–507 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9