Advertisement

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences

, Volume 5, Issue 1, pp 31–52 | Cite as

Folk psychology’ is not folk psychology

  • Matthew Ratcliffe
Article

Abstract

This paper disputes the claim that our understanding of others is enabled by a commonsense or ‘folk’ psychology, whose ‘core’ involves the attribution of intentional states in order to predict and explain behaviour. I argue that interpersonal understanding is seldom, if ever, a matter of two people assigning intentional states to each other but emerges out of a context of interaction between them. Self and other form a coupled system rather than two wholly separate entities equipped with an internalised capacity to assign mental states to the other. This applies even in those instances where one might seem to adopt a ‘detached’ perspective towards others. Thus ‘folk psychology’, as commonly construed, is not folk psychology.

Keywords

extended cognition folk psychology interaction intersubjectivity 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Baker, L. R. 1991. What is this Thing called “Commonsense Psychology”? Philosophical Explorations 2: 3–19.Google Scholar
  2. Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge Mass, London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. Baron-Cohen, S. and Swettenham, J. 1996. In: Carruthers and Smith (eds), The Relationship between SAM and ToMM: Two Hypotheses. (pp. 158–168).Google Scholar
  4. Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg, H. and Cohen, D. J. (eds). 1993. Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Broom, P. and German, T. P. 2000. Two Reasons to abandon the False Belief Task as a Test of Theory of Mind. Cognition 77: B25–B31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bruner, J. and Feldman, C. 1993. In: Baron-Cohen et al. (eds), Theories of Mind and the Problem of Autism, (pp. 267–291).Google Scholar
  7. Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. K. (eds), 1996. Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Churchland, P. M. 1998b. Evaluating our Self Conception. In Churchland and Churchland: 25–38.Google Scholar
  9. Churchland, P. M. and Churchland, P. S. 1998. On the Contrary: Critical Essays, Cambridge MA, London: MIT Press, 1987–1997.Google Scholar
  10. Clark, A. 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. London, Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Clark, A. 2001. Reasons, Robots and the Extended Mind. Mind and Language 16(2): 121–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. 1998. The Extended Mind. Analysis 58: 7–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Cole, J. 1998. About Face. Cambridge Mass., London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Cole, J. 2001a. In: Thompson (ed.), Empathy needs a Face, (pp. 51–68).Google Scholar
  15. Cole, J. 2001b. In: Kaszniak (ed), The Contribution of the Face in the Development of Emotion and Self, (pp. 478–482).Google Scholar
  16. Currie, G. and Sterelny, K. 2000. How to think about the Modularity of Mind-Reading. Philosophical Quarterly 50: 143–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds), 1995a. Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds), 1995b. Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Frith, U. and Happ'e, F. 1999. Theory of Mind and Self-Consciousness: What is it like to be Autistic? Mind and Language 14: 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gallagher, S. 2001a. In: Thompson (ed), The Practice of Mind: Theory, Simulation, or Interaction? (pp. 83–108).Google Scholar
  21. Gallagher, S. 2001b. In: Kaszniak (ed), Emotion and Intersubjective Perception: A Speculative Account, (pp. 95–100).Google Scholar
  22. Gallese, V. and Goldman, A. 1998. Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind-Reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2: 493–501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gallese, V. 2001. In: Thompson (ed), The ‘Shared Manifold’ Hypothesis: From Mirror Neurons to Empathy, (pp. 33–50).Google Scholar
  24. Garfield, J. L., Peterson, C. C. and Perry, T. 2001. Social Cognition, Language Acquisition and the Development of the Theory of Mind. Mind and Language 16: 494–541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Gerrans, P. 2002. The theory of mind module in evolutionary psychology. Biology and Philosophy 17: 305–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Goldie, P. 1999. How we think of others’ emotions. Mind and Language 14: 394–423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Goldie, P. 2000. The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  28. Gopnik, A. 1996. In: Carruthers and Smith (eds), Theories and Modules: Creation Myths, Developmental Realities, and Neurath's Boat, (pp. 169–183).Google Scholar
  29. Gordon, R. 1995. In: Davies and Stone (eds), Folk Psychology as Simulation. (a), (pp. 60–73).Google Scholar
  30. Gordon, R. 1996. In: Carruthers and Smith (eds), “Radical” Simulation, (pp. 11–21).Google Scholar
  31. Heal, J. 1996. In: Carruthers and Smith (eds), Simulation, Theory and Content, (pp. 75–89).Google Scholar
  32. Heidegger, M. 1962. Being and Time (trans. J. MacQuarrie and E. Robinson). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  33. Husserl, E. 1960. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology (trans. D. Cairns). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  34. Husserl, E. 1970. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (trans. D. Carr). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Kaszniak, A. ed, 2001. Emotion, Qualia and Consciousness. Singapore, New Jersey, London, Hong Kong: World Scientific.Google Scholar
  36. Langdon. R., Davies, M. and Coltheart, M. 2002. Understanding Mind and Understanding Communicated Meanings in Schizophrenia. Mind and Language 17: 68–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. McGeer, V. 2001. In: Thompson (ed), Psycho-practice, Psycho-Theory and the Contrastive Case of Autism: How Practices of Mind become Second-Nature, (pp. 109–132).Google Scholar
  38. Ratcliffe, M. J. forthcoming. Rethinking Commonsense Psychology. London: Palgrave.Google Scholar
  39. Ravenscroft, I. 1998. What is it like to be Someone Else? Simulation and Empathy. Ratio XI: 170–185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Rizzolatti, G. and Arbib, M. A. 1998. Language within our Grasp. Trends in Neuroscience 21(5): 188–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Segal, G. 1996. In: Carruthers and Smith (eds), The Modularity of Theory of Mind, (pp. 141–157).Google Scholar
  42. Sellars, W. 1956. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science I. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  43. Scholl, B. J. and Leslie, A. M. 1999. Modularity, Development and ‘Theory of Mind’. Mind and Language 14: 131–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Stich, S. and Ravenscroft, I. 1996. What is folk psychology? In Stich's Deconstructing the Mind. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Stone, T. and Davies, M. 1996. In: Carruthers and Smith (eds), The Mental Simulation Debate: A Progress Report, (pp. 119–137).Google Scholar
  46. Thompson, E. 2001. In: Thompson (ed), Empathy and Consciousness, 1–31.Google Scholar
  47. Thompson, E. (ed), 2001. Between Ourselves: Second-Person Issues in the Study of Consciousness. Thornton, UK: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  48. Wimmer, H. and Perner, J. 1983. Beliefs about Beliefs: Representation and Constraining Function of Wrong Beliefs in Young Children's Understanding of Deception. Cognition 13: 103–128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, Inc. 2005

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of DurhamDurhamUK

Personalised recommendations