Skip to main content

Advertisement

SpringerLink
  1. Home
  2. Natural Language Semantics
  3. Article
The Question–Answer Requirement for scope assignment
Download PDF
Your article has downloaded

Similar articles being viewed by others

Slider with three articles shown per slide. Use the Previous and Next buttons to navigate the slides or the slide controller buttons at the end to navigate through each slide.

Negative clauses imply affirmative topics and affirmative antecedents

07 August 2021

Charles Clifton Jr., Lyn Frazier & Barbara Kaup

Truth predicates, truth bearers, and their variants

19 June 2018

Friederike Moltmann

Presuppositions, implicatures, and contextual equivalence

08 April 2021

Paul Marty & Jacopo Romoli

Contrary to Expectations: Does Context Influence the Processing Cost Associated with Negation?

27 July 2021

Elena Albu, Oksana Tsaregorodtseva & Barbara Kaup

Irony as a Test of the Presupposition-Denial Account: An ERP Study

20 August 2021

Ruth Filik, Joanne Ingram, … Hartmut Leuthold

How important are truth-conditions for truth-conditional semantics?

10 April 2019

Toby Napoletano

On the syntax of rhetorical questions: evidence from Cantonese

27 September 2022

Sze-Wing Tang

The Diverse Landscape of Negative Polarity Items: On the Use of German NPIs as Experimental Diagnostics

26 July 2021

Katharina Schaebbicke, Heiko Seeliger & Sophie Repp

How I Really Say What You Think

09 November 2019

José Manuel Viejo

Download PDF
  • Open Access
  • Published: 20 May 2008

The Question–Answer Requirement for scope assignment

  • Andrea Gualmini1,
  • Sarah Hulsey2,3,
  • Valentine Hacquard4 &
  • …
  • Danny Fox2 

Natural Language Semantics volume 16, pages 205–237 (2008)Cite this article

  • 1097 Accesses

  • 63 Citations

  • Metrics details

Abstract

This paper focuses on children’s interpretation of sentences containing negation and a quantifier (e.g., The detective didn’t find some guys). Recent studies suggest that, although children are capable of accessing inverse scope interpretations of such sentences, they resort to surface scope to a larger extent than adults. To account for children’s behavioral pattern, we propose a new factor at play in Truth Value Judgment tasks: the Question–Answer Requirement (QAR). According to the QAR, children (and adults) must interpret the target sentence that they evaluate as an answer to a question that is made salient by the discourse.

Download to read the full article text

Working on a manuscript?

Avoid the most common mistakes and prepare your manuscript for journal editors.

Learn more

References

  • Chierchia, Gennaro, Stephen Crain, Maria Teresa Guasti, and Rosalind Thornton. 1998. Some and or: a study on the emergence of logical form. In Proceedings of the 22th Boston University Conference on language development, 97–108. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.

  • Collingwood Robin George. (1940). An essay on metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Janet Dean Fodor., Crain and Stephen (1987). Sentence matching and overgeneration. Cognition 26: 123–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crain, Stephen, and Cecile McKee. 1985. The acquisition of structural restrictions on anaphora. In Proceedings of NELS 15, 94–110. Amherst: GLSA.

  • Rosalind Thornton., Crain and Stephen (1998). Investigations in Universal Grammar. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosalind Thornton, Carole Boster, Laura Conway, Lillo-Martin Diane C., Elaine Woodams., Crain and Stephen (1996). Quantification without qualification. Language Acquisition 5: 83–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson Donald. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Helen Tager Flusberg. and de Villiers Jill (1975). Some facts one simply cannot deny. Journal of Child Language 2: 373–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felber, Sarah. 2002. Acquisition of two alleged polarity items: the convergence of children and adults in some and any judgments. Ms., University of Connecticut.

  • Grice, Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and Semantics, ed. Peter Cole and James Morgan, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.

  • Groenendijk, Jeroen, and Martin Stokhof. 1984. Studies on the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. PhD dissertation, University of Amsterdam.

  • Gualmini Andrea. (2004a). Some knowledge children don’t lack. Linguistics 42: 957–982

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gualmini Andrea. (2004b). The ups and downs of child language. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Maria Teresa, Gennaro Chierchia, Stephen Crain, Francesca Foppolo, Andrea Gualmini, Luisa Meroni. and Guasti (2005). Why children and adults sometimes (but not always) compute implicatures. Language and Cognitive Processes 20: 667–696

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charles Leonard. and Hamblin (1973). Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language 10: 41–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn Laurence R. (1989). A natural history of negation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Krämer, Irene. 2000. Interpreting indefinites. PhD dissertation, Utrecht University.

  • Ladusaw, William. 1979. Polarity sensitivity as inherent scope relations. PhD dissertation, University of Texas at Austin.

  • Julien Musolino., Lidz and Jeffrey (2002). Children’s command of quantification. Cognition 84: 113–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maratsos and Michael. (1976). The use of definite and indefinite reference in young children. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dana Fox, Judith Becker, Mary Anne Chalkley, Maratsos and Michael (1985). Semantic restrictions on children’s passives. Cognition 19: 167–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Karen, and Cristina Schmitt. 2004. Wide-scope indefinites in English child language. In Proceedings of GALA, 317–328. Utrecht: LOT.

  • Milsark and Gary. (1977). Towards an explanation of certain peculiarities of the existential construction in English. Linguistic Analysis 3: 1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Musolino, Julien. 1998. Universal Grammar and the acquisition of semantic knowledge. PhD dissertation, University of Maryland.

  • Musolino, Julien. 2006. Structure and meaning in the acquisition of scope. In Semantics in acquisition, ed. Veerle van Geenhoven, 141–166. New York: Springer.

  • Andrea Gualmini., Musolino and Julien (2004). The role of partitivity in child language. Language Acquisition 12: 97–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musolino, Julien, and Jeffrey Lidz. 2002. Preschool logic: truth and felicity in the acquisition of quantification. In Proceedings of the Boston University Conference of language acquisition, vol. 26, 406–416. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.

  • Jeffrey Lidz., Musolino and Julien (2003). The scope of isomorphism: turning adults into children. Language Acquisition 11: 277–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey Lidz., Musolino and Julien (2006). Why children aren’t universally successful with quantification. Linguistics 44: 817–852

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephen Crain, Rosalind Thornton., Musolino and Julien (2000). Navigating negative quantificational space. Linguistics 38: 1–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart and Tanya. (2006). Interface strategies. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • John C., Irina Sekerina, Nicole Hill, Marian Logrip. and Trueswell (1999). The kindergarten-path effect: studying online sentence processing in young children. Cognition 73: 89–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, Kai. 1994. Restrictions on quantifier domains. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Wason and Peter. (1972). The context of plausible denial. Journal of Verbal Learning and Language Behavior 4: 7–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yang and Charles. (2002). Knowledge and learning in natural language. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Open Access

This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Noncommercial License which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

  1. Utrecht Institute of Linguistics, OTS, Janskerkhof 13, 3512 BL, Utrecht, The Netherlands

    Andrea Gualmini

  2. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, MIT, 77 Massachusetts Avenue, Cambridge, MA, 02139, USA

    Sarah Hulsey & Danny Fox

  3. Linguistics Program, Northeastern University, 360 Huntington Avenue, Boston, MA, 02115, USA

    Sarah Hulsey

  4. Department of Linguistics, University of Maryland, 1401 Marie Mount Hall, College Park, MD, 20742, USA

    Valentine Hacquard

Authors
  1. Andrea Gualmini
    View author publications

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

  2. Sarah Hulsey
    View author publications

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

  3. Valentine Hacquard
    View author publications

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

  4. Danny Fox
    View author publications

    You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Gualmini.

Additional information

Among many others, we would like to thank Stephen Crain, Ivano Caponigro, Aniko Csirmaz, Irene Heim, Luisa Meroni, Julien Musolino, Andrew Nevins, Carson Schütze, Bernhard Schwarz, and Ken Wexler, as well as the participants in seminar 24.979 at MIT in the fall of 2003, as well as two anonymous reviewers. Thanks also to the teachers, parents, and children at Open Center for Children and Bright Future (Somerville, MA), Bright Horizons Old West Church (Boston, MA), the Volpe Center, Bright Horizons One Kendall Square and Technology Children’s Center (Cambridge, MA), Center for Young Children (College Park, MD), Jardin D’Enfants NDG, Playskool and YMCA Westmount daycare (Montréal, QC). Andrea Gualmini’s research was partially supported by a McGill VP-Research internal grant, a Standard Research Grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC), and by a VIDI grant from the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) and Utrecht University.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Noncommercial License (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/2.0), which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited.

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gualmini, A., Hulsey, S., Hacquard, V. et al. The Question–Answer Requirement for scope assignment. Nat Lang Semantics 16, 205–237 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-008-9029-z

Download citation

  • Published: 20 May 2008

  • Issue Date: September 2008

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-008-9029-z

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

Keywords

  • Language acquisition
  • Negation
  • Scope ambiguities
  • Ambiguity resolution
Download PDF

Working on a manuscript?

Avoid the most common mistakes and prepare your manuscript for journal editors.

Learn more

Advertisement

Over 10 million scientific documents at your fingertips

Switch Edition
  • Academic Edition
  • Corporate Edition
  • Home
  • Impressum
  • Legal information
  • Privacy statement
  • California Privacy Statement
  • How we use cookies
  • Manage cookies/Do not sell my data
  • Accessibility
  • FAQ
  • Contact us
  • Affiliate program

Not affiliated

Springer Nature

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG. Part of Springer Nature.