Skip to main content
Log in

What about lexical semantics if syntax is the only generative component of the grammar?

A case study on word meaning in German

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper explores the semantic consequences of the principle of containment embodied by the popular assumption that word formation is entirely syntactic and that there is no generative lexicon. According to the principle of containment, the analysis and structure of a given form must also be contained within the analysis of any structure derived from that form. The implications of the containment principle for the analysis of word meaning are elucidated with a detailed case study of ambiguous German nominalizations. The resulting analysis of ambiguous German nominalizations is employed as a probe into the structure and analysis of contained constructions to derive novel insights about the syntax and semantics of adjectival participles in German.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It should be noted that because the syntactic analysis of a seemingly idiomatic meaning does not differ from the syntactic analysis of a compositional meaning, the containment principle obtains regardless of whether or not the meaning of a structure is idiomatic.

  2. Like Harley, Alexiadou (2009), gives up on the embedded vP hypothesis: “the difference between AS [Argument Structure] and non-AS nominals does not depend on the presence of verbalizing morphology” (Alexiadou 2009:256). Borer (2003) keeps the embedded vP hypothesis but gives up on containment: the result reading is not derived in the syntax but roots like √exam “may be associated, in the L-D [lexical phrasal domain], with an inserted nominal (and verbalizing) affix” (Borer 2003:52).

  3. For a similarly critical inspection of Grimshaw’s claims with respect to English nominalizations see e.g. Newmeyer (2009), Grimm and McNally (2013).

  4. I use the following glossing conventions for German examples: NMLZ = Nominalization, PRFX = Prefix, PRTC = Particle, PTCTP = Participle, GEN = genitive. I indicate the selection restrictions of a predicate with a superscript: E (event), S (state), O (object). When there is no suitable translation of a German be-prefixed construction into English, I indicate the be-prefix also in the translation.

  5. As a reviewer notes, an anaphoric description of a state as in (25) appears to be compatible with the selection restrictions of renovieren if the second sentence starts with a temporal sequence connective like danach (‘after that’). But in contrast to (26), the temporal connective in (25) enforces an interpretation of the anaphoric construction according to which the state to which the anaphoric construction refers back is not the state in which the wall painting was before the renovation but rather is the result state entailed by the verb to renovate that the wall is in after and because of the renovation. Thus, the acceptability of (25) is due to the temporal connective picking up the change of state entailment of renovieren and as such is independent of the selection restrictions of renovieren.

    1. (25)
      figure i
  6. “The exact (semantic) categories for roots that predicts their varying behavior in nominal and verbal environments is not important here (although identifying these categories is of course essential to syntactic theory). The important point is that there are such categories” (Marantz 1997:216).

  7. The spell-out rules in (46) simply circumvents the problem of the distribution of the -t morpheme in verbal conjugation by assuming that the spell-out of the [+part] feature is empty in contexts other than +a and +Pred. A reviewer suggested that a more thorough investigation may be able to come up with a systematic explanation of the distribution of the -t morpheme (which is not realized in the 1.SG/1.PL/3.PL present tense conjugation) in analogy to the systematic explanation of the seemingly idiosyncratic t-stem in Latin argued for in Steriade (2016), where—quite similar to my case—“some verbal derivatives have a stem that is identical to that of the perfect-passive participle” (Steriade 2016:114).

  8. The proposed analysis of adjectival participles relates to Maienborn (2005) and subsequent work in a straightforward way. Maienborn argues that states denoted by copula constructions (like adjectival participles) are ‘Kimian States,’ states that are ontologically poorer than ‘Neo-Davidsonian’ states. Kimian states are not defined relative to a (Neo-)Davidsonian event but “are to be understood as reifications for the exemplification of a property Q at a holder x and a time t.” (Maienborn 2009:41), which is nothing other than the state derived with PredP.

  9. 2016, Inverted Classroom and Beyond: Lehren und Lernen im 21. Jahrhundert, eds. Großkurth, Handke. Marburg: tectum Verlag.

  10. I should add here that event-related modifiers (McIntyre 2015:941) “are unacceptable in adjectival participles unless they contribute to the description of the state expressed by the participle or of the theme during the interval during which this state holds.” Low participles denote states and thus are compatible with approaches to event-related modifiers in the literature like the incorporation approach of Gehrke (2015) and the Kimian state analysis of Maienborn (2009); see also fn. 11.

  11. Such a revision of the licensing condition for ung-nominalizations would also account for the last construction type of verbs in German I didn’t address at all, namely particle verbs. Following Roßdeutscher (2016), German particles like ab (‘off’) have a scalar semantics similar to that of scalar adjectives. And interestingly, mono-eventive verbs like arbeiten have an ung-nominalization (and thus are bi-eventive) in the presence of such a scalar particle as in (79b).

    1. (79)
      figure an

References

  • Ackema, Peter, and Ad Neeleman. 2004. Beyond morphology: Interface conditions on word formation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis. 2001. Functional structure in nominals: Nominalization and ergativity. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis. 2009. On the role of syntactic locality in morphological processes: The case of (Greek) derived nominals. In Quantification, definiteness, and nominalization, eds. Anastasia Giannakidou and Monika Rathert, 253–280. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis, and Gianina Iordǎchioaia. 2014. Two syntactic strategies to derive deadjectival nominalizations. Anglica Wratislaviensia 52: 65–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, Nicholas. 2011. Lexical meaning in context: A web of words. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, Nicholas, and James Pustejovsky. 2006. A type composition logic for the generative lexicon. Journal of Cognitive Science 6: 1–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Emmon. 1986. Natural language metaphysics. In Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science 7, eds. Ruth Barcan Marcus, Georg J. W. Dorn, and Paul Weingartner, 573–595. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark. 1988. Incorporation. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bǎsić, Monika. 2010. On the morphological make-up of nominalizations in Serbian. In The syntax of nominalizations across languages and frameworks, eds. Artemis Alexiadou and Monika Rathert, 39–66. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beavers, John, and Andrew Koontz-Garboden. 2017. Change of state verbs and the semantics of roots. In West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL) 34, 347–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bierwisch, Manfred. 1989. Event nominalizations: Proposals and problems. Linguistische Studien A 194: 1–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bierwisch, Manfred. 2007. Semantic form as interface. In Interfaces and interface conditions, ed. Andreas Späth, 1–32. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borer, Hagit. 1999. Deconstructing the construct. In Beyond principles and parameters, eds. Kyle Johnson and Ian G. Roberts, 43–89. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Borer, Hagit. 2003. Exo-skeletal vs. endo-skeletal explanations. In The nature of explanation in linguistic theory, eds. John Moore and Maria Polinsky, 31–67. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borer, Hagit. 2005. Structuring sense (vol. 1 and 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Borer, Hagit. 2013. Structuring sense (vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruening, Benjamin. 2014. Word formation is syntactic: Adjectival passives in English. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 32 (2): 363–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1967. The logical form of action sentences. In The logic and decision of action, ed. Nicholas Rescher, 81–95. Pittsburgh: The University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demske, Ulrike. 2002. Nominalization and argument structure in early new high German. In Nominalization, eds. Ewald Lang and Ilse Zimmermann, Vol. 27, 67–90. Berlin: ZAS Papers in Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewell, Robert B. 2015. The semantics of German verb prefixes. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, David. R. 1979. Word meaning and Montague grammar. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrich, Veronika, and Irene Rapp. 2000. Sortale Bedeutung und Argumentstruktur: ung-Nominalisierungen im Deutschen. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 19 (2): 245–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Embick, David. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic Inquiry 35: 355–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Embick, David. 2009. Roots, states, and stative passives. Handout presented at the Roots Workshop, University of Stuttgart.

  • Francez, Itamar, and Andrew Koontz-Garboden. 2017. Semantics and morphosyntactic variation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrke, Berit. 2015. Adjectival participles, event kind modification and pseudo-incorporation. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 33 (3): 897–938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, Scott, and Louise McNally. 2013. No ordered arguments needed for nouns. In 19th Amsterdam colloquium, eds. Maria Aloni, Michael Franke, and Floris Roelofsen, 123–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimshaw, Jane. 1990. Argument structure. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Günther, Hartmut. 1974. Das System der Verben mit be- in der deutschen Sprache der Gegenwart. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halle, Morris, and Alec Marantz. 1993. Distributed morphology and the pieces of inflection. In The view from building 20: Essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvian Bromberger, eds. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Kaiser, 111–176. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamm, Fritz, and Torgrim Solstad. 2010. Reambiguation: On the non-monotonicity of disambiguation. In Empirical issues in syntax and semantics, eds. Oliver Bonami and Patricia Cabredo Hofherr, Vol. 8, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harley, Heidi. 2009. The morphology of nominalizations and the syntax of vP. In Quantification, definiteness, and nominalization, eds. Anastasia Giannakidou and Monika Rathert. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harley, Heidi. 2011. A minimalist approach of argument structure. In The Oxford handbook of linguistic minimalism, ed. Cedric Boeckx. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harley, Heidi. 2013. Semantics in distributed morphology. In Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning, eds. Claudia Maienborn, Klaus von Heusinger, and Paul Portner. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, Ray. 1988. Conceptual semantics. In Meaning and mental representations, eds. Umberto Eco, Marco Santambrogio, and Patrizia Violi, 81–97. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, Hans, Josef van Genabith, and Uwe Reyle. 2011. Discourse representation theory. In Handbook of philosophical logic, eds. Dov M. Gabbay and Franz Guenthner, Vol. 15, 125–394. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Chris, and Beth Levin. 2008. Measure of change: The adjectival core of degree achievements. In Adjectives and adverbs: Syntax, semantics and discourse, eds. Louise McNally and Chris Kennedy, 156–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2000. Building statives. In Annual meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (BLS) 26, 385–399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2005. Building resultatives. In Event arguments: Foundations and applications, eds. Claudia Maienbaum and Angelika Wöllstein-Leisten. Tübingen: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth. 1993. English verb classes and alternations: A preliminary investigation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth. 1999. Objecthood: An event structure perspective. In Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 35, 223–247. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport. 1986. The formation of adjectival passives. Linguistic Inquiry 17: 623–661.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity at the syntax-semantics interface. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienborn, Claudia. 2005. On the limits of the Davidsonian approach: The case of copula sentences. Theoretical Linguistics 31 (3): 275–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienborn, Claudia. 2007. On Davidsonian and Kimian states. In Existence: Syntax and semantics, eds. Ileana Comorovski and Klaus von Heusinger, 107–130. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienborn, Claudia. 2009. Building event-based ad hoc properties: On the interpretation of adjectival passives. In Sinn und Bedeutung 13, eds. Arndt Riester and Torgrim Solstad, 31–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. In University of Pennsylvania working papers in linguistics, Vol. 4, Issue 2, Article 14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marantz, Alec. 2005. Objects out of the lexicon: Objects as events. Handout presented at the University of Vienna. Available at web.mit.edu/marantz/Public/Vienna/Vienna.pdf. Accessed 30 March 2018.

  • McIntyre, Andrew. 2015. Event modifiers in (German) adjectival participles: Remarks on Gehrke. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 33: 939–953.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, Richard. 1973. The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. Approaches to Natural Language 49: 221–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myler, Neil. 2016. Building and interpreting possession sentences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newmeyer, Frederick. 2009. Current challenges to the lexicalist hypothesis. In Time and again: Theoretical perspectives on formal linguistics. In honor of D. Terence Langendoen, eds. William D. Lewis, Simin Karimi, Heidi Harley, and Scott O. Farrar, 91–117. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, Francesco, and Chris Swoyer. 2016. Properties, Winter 2016 edn. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford University: Metaphysics Research Lab.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pross, Tillmann. 2015. Mono-eventive verbs of emission and their bi-eventive nominalizations. In North East Linguistic Society (NELS) 45, eds. Thui Buy and Denis Özyıldız, Vol. 1, 257–266. Amherst: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, James. 1995. The generative lexicon. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramchand, Gillian. 2008. Verb meaning and the lexicon: A first phase syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport Hovav, Malka, and Beth Levin. 1998. Building verb meanings. In The projection of arguments: Lexical and compositional factors, eds. Miriam Butt and Willi Geuder, 97–134. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans. 1947. Elements of symbolic logic. London: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roßdeutscher, Antje. 2010. German -ung-formation: An explanation of formation and interpretation in a root-based account. Linguistische Berichte. Sonderheft 17: 101–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roßdeutscher, Antje. 2016. Scale based particles and prefixes in German de-adjectival verbs. Handout presented at the Workshop on Aspect and Argument Structure of Adjectives and Participles (WAASAP) 3, University of Lille 3.

  • Roßdeutscher, Antje, and Hans Kamp. 2010. Syntactic and semantic constraints on the formation and interpretation of ung-Nouns. In Nominalisations across languages and frameworks, eds. Artemis Alexiadou and Monika Rathert. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy, Isabelle. 2010. Deadjectival nominalizations and the structure of the adjective. In The syntax of nominalizations across languages and frameworks, eds. Artemis Alexiadou and Monika Rathert. 129–158. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Starke, Michael. 2009. Nanosyntax: A short primer to a new approach to language. Nordlyd 36 (1): 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stassen, Leon. 2009. Predicative possession. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steriade, Donca. 2016. The morphome vs similarity-based syncretism: The Latin t-stem derivative. In The morphome debate, eds. Ana Luís and Ricardo Bermúdez-Otero, 112–172. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, Lisa. 1984. Parameters and effects of word order variation. PhD diss., MIT.

  • van Hout, Angeliek, and Tom Roeper. 1998. Events and aspectual structure in distributed morphology. In Roundtable on argument structure and aspect, ed. Heidi Harley, 175–199. Cambridge MITWPL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Zeno. 1967. Facts and events. In Linguistics in philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Stechow, Arnim. 1996. The different readings of wieder ‘again’: A structural account. Journal of Semantics 13: 87–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wasow, Thomas. 1977. Transformations and the lexicon. In Formal syntax, eds. Peter Culicover, Adrian Akmajian, and Thomas Wasow, 327–360. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wunderlich, Dieter. 1987. An investigation of lexical composition: The case of German be- verbs. Linguistics 25: 283–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the handling editor Gillian Ramchand and three anonymous reviewers for having carefully read earlier versions of the paper. The paper profited very much from their instructive and detailed comments. I am also indebted to the reviewers and participants of the 3rd Workshop on Aspect and Argument Structure of Adjectives and Participles (WASAAP 3), the 6th Workshop on Nominalizations (JeNom 6) as well as the participants of the syntax/semantics research group at the University of Texas at Austin for helpful comments on earlier versions of the paper. I would particularly like to thank Antje Roßdeutscher and Hans Kamp for reading and commenting on numerous earlier versions of the paper. All remaining errors are my own. The research reported in this paper was supported by a grant of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) to the project B4 “Lexikalische Information und ihre Entfaltung im Kontext von Wortbildung, Satz und Diskurs,” as part of the Collaborative Research Center SFB 732 “Incremental Specification in Context.”

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tillmann Pross.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pross, T. What about lexical semantics if syntax is the only generative component of the grammar?. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 37, 215–261 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-9410-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-9410-7

Keywords

Navigation