Skip to main content
Log in

Parameterizing split ergativity in Mayan

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to explain the variation of Case alignment in the accusative side of the ergative split of Kaqchikel, Chol and Q’anjob’al (Mayan). In particular, I will address contrastive alignments found in their accusative side. In the accusative side of Kaqchikel, the intransitive subject and the transitive subject alike are cross-referenced by the absolutive morpheme (also known as the set B marker in Mayan linguistics). On the other hand, the object of a transitive verb is cross-referenced by the ergative morpheme (or the set A marker). In the accusative side of Chol and Q’anjob’al, by contrast, both the intransitive subject and the transitive subject are cross-referenced by the set A marker, while the set B marker cross-references the transitive object. This contrast is unexpected, given that these languages have a (nearly) identical biclausal structure for their accusative side, as I will claim building on Laka (2006) and Coon (2010a, 2013a): the aspectual predicate forms a biclausal structure with a nominalized clause. I will argue that the contrastive alignments found in Kaqchikel, Chol and Q’anjob’al follow from a parametric difference regarding the nominalization involved in the accusative side of these languages. It will be proposed that the Restriction on Nominalization (RON) holds for Kaqchikel, whereas it does not apply to Chol and Q’anjob’al: the nominalized verb must lack a syntactically projected external argument. The RON will be developed, based on a similar observation made for nominalizations in Greek and some Indo-European languages among others (Alexiadou 2001). As will be demonstrated, the presence or absence of the RON and the type of alignment patterns in the accusative side of the ergative split are causally connected.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The following abbreviations will be used, based on the Leipzig glossing rules (some glosses are added): 1 = first person; 2 = second person; 3 = third person; A = set A (ergative/genitive) marker; AF = Agent Focus (morpheme); ANTIP = antipassive morpheme; B = set B (absolutive) marker; CAUS = causative suffix; CL = proper name clitic; DET = determiner; DM = dependent marker; INDF = indefinite article; INTR = intransitive status suffix; IPFV = imperfective aspect; NEG = negation; NMLZ = nominalizing suffix; PASS = passive (morpheme); PL = plural (suffix); PREP = preposition; PROG = progressive aspect; PFV = perfective aspect; RN = relational noun; RTV = root transitive status suffix; SG = singular; TR = transitive status suffix.

  2. As England (1991) writes, “Kaqchikel is the language of the K’ichean branch that is perhaps the most insistent on SVO order today” (England 1991:472).

  3. Clemens (2013) finds that verb-initial word order (with rising intonation) in simple sentences is understood as a polar question. Clemens also observes that the Patzún dialect of Kaqchikel allows VOS order as well as SVO order for transitive sentences in embedded contexts.

  4. Conventionally, split ergativity is discussed for morphologically ergative languages rather than syntactically ergative languages, as Coon (2013b) correctly puts. We will follow this convention and focus on morphological (split) ergativity.

  5. The alternation between y- and n- in Kaqchikel is governed by the presence or absence of an overt set B marker. The imperfective marker n- is used when a null set B marker (= ø) appears: i.e., when the morpheme cross-references third person singular. The imperfective marker y- is used elsewhere.

  6. Although not only non-finite clauses but finite clauses may appear with the progressive marker ajin (and the embedding verb chäp ‘begin’), we will focus on the variant with nominalized non-finite clauses throughout the paper. The finite clause occurring with ajin and chäp displays a regular ergative alignment, as shown below: the bracketed form is a finite clause.

    1. (i)
      figure k

    This further suggests that split ergativity in Kaqchikel results from structural differences associated with aspect. A particular restriction on nominalization that I will propose in Sect. 3 only applies to non-finite clauses, as they undergo nominalization. I thank an anonymous reviewer for the clarification.

  7. All transitive verbs can be suffixed by -ïk, whereas intransitive verbs only in certain dialects can be nominalized with -ïk (Brown et al. 2006): it appears that only a subgroup of intransitive verbs can be suffixed by it even in these dialects. The intransitives that resist -ïk appear to be suffixed by Vn, though further research is necessary on this (see Imanishi and Mateo Pedro 2013 for relevant discussion). The other nominalizing suffix -oj may be suffixed to both transitive and intransitive verbs.

  8. We will observe below that some nominalized forms with -ïk do not bear the set A marker.

  9. The use of ri, which appears before the finite verb as seen in (25) and (64), is arguably a complementizer or relativizer (see also Brown et al. 2006 and Erlewine 2016).

  10. For reasons unknown to me, the nominalized form with -ïk is degraded with the set A marker (i.e., ru-) in (25).

  11. The prefix aj- is historically a gender marker for masculine, whereas x- is for feminine (I thank Jessica Coon for pointing this out to me). Jessica Coon (p.c.) has also informed me that gender markers in Mayan are generally incompatible with set A (= ergative and genitive) markers.

  12. I thank David Pesetsky for bringing this work to my attention.

  13. Note that one of my Kaqchikel consultants reported that (45) and (46) sound better than their reverse word order, but are still not good. For the consultant reporting the ungrammaticality of (45) and (46), the opposite holds: their reverse word order sounds better, but is still not good. Importantly, nominalized verbs behave on a par with verbs (but not nouns) in that they perfectly allow adverbs: (42)–(44). I leave a particular analysis of adverbs’ position in Kaqchikel nominals including nominalizations for further research.

  14. In the dialect of Kaqchikel discussed by García Matzar and Rodríguez Guaján (1997), the vowel of the nominalizing suffix is tensed, unlike in the dialect of my consultants.

  15. See Imanishi (2014) for certain differences between Kaqchikel and Chol/Q’anjob’al regarding a range of nominal properties of nominalized verbs in these languages.

  16. The exact labels of the projections within a verbal domain are irrelevant—VP, VoiceP and vP are all extended projections of a verb in the sense of Grimshaw (1991).

  17. It has been proposed by works such as Harley (2013) and Legate (2014) that VoiceP is higher than vP, an inverse of the hierarchical organization in (51). Based on the investigation of status suffixes of Mayan languages, by contrast, Coon et al. (2014) argue that the structure as shown in (51) is needed for these languages.

  18. These status suffixes only appear in phrase-final position (Mateo Toledo 2008).

  19. I do not attempt to provide an analysis of morphological realization of agreement morphemes, as it will go beyond the scope of the paper. For example, Preminger (2011, 2014) argues that set B markers (= absolutive morphemes) in some Mayan languages such as Kaqchikel, K’ichee’ and Tz’utujil (= the Kichean branch) are derived via clitic doubling of the full absolutive DP (see the references for details).

  20. To be precise, Legate (2008) proposes a new view that there is no absolutive Case in the syntax. She argues that absolutive Case is a morphological default: a cover term for case that does not have a dedicated morphological form. In one type of languages called absolutive as a morphological default (ABS = DEF), as she proposes, “absolutive” Case is assigned by either T (= nominative) in intransitives or v (= accusative) in transitives in the syntax just as in familiar languages like English. In the morphology, however, nominative/accusative Case is realized as the null default in many ergative languages. Legate claims that this conflation of nominative and accusative into the default morphological case is the source of absolutive Case. In the other type of languages called absolutive as nominative (ABS = NOM) under Legate’s system, “absolutive” Case is the nominative uniformly assigned by T (or a higher functional head), as has been proposed by Murasugi (1992), Bittner and Hale (1996a,b), Ura (2000, 2001) among others.

  21. There is further division when we consider non-verbal predicates. For example, the set B marker in some Mayan languages such as Q’eqchi’ (Berinstein 1985; DeChicchis 1989) and Q’anjob’al (Coon et al. 2014) is “high” in verbal predicates, whereas it is “low” in non-verbal predicates such as copular sentences—the set B marker follows the predicative noun.

  22. The main purpose of Coon et al. (2014) is to explain a ban on extraction of the ergative subject in some Mayan languages, based on locality properties of absolutive Case assignment: in order to extract the ergative subject, these languages must employ special verbal morphology called Agent Focus morphology as a circumventing strategy.

  23. There is simply a notational difference between (57) and the Mayan Absolutive Parameter (Coon et al. 2011, 2014). Voice in (57) corresponds to v in the latter.

  24. It has been suggested by previous works such as Bok-Bennema (1991) that the inability of a transitive verb to assign Case is a defining character of ergative languages in opposition to accusative languages. However, a transitive verb in some ergative languages, such as low absolutive languages of Mayan, assigns Case just as in accusative languages (see also Aldridge 2004, 2008; Legate 2008).

  25. In this respect, we depart from Coon et al. (2014): they argue that the object and the intransitive subject in high absolutive languages move to the edge of vP, from which they receive absolutive Case from Infl. This avoids the trapping of these elements inside the Spell-Out domain of vP.

  26. This contrasts with English nominalizations where the agent may be not only introduced as the by-phrase but also genitive-marked, whereas the internal argument is introduced by of: e.g., Rome’s destruction of the city and the destruction of the city by Rome. The internal argument may also be genitive-marked (= passive nominals): the city’s destruction (see Alexiadou 2001 for relevant discussion). As will be shown in (64), by contrast, the agent of the nominalized verb in Kaqchikel appears as part of the relative clause modifying the nominalized clause. While I am unable to provide an analysis of why this difference arises in this paper, it is worth noting that languages differ as to how the (counterpart of) by-phrase appears, depending on the type of nominals, as pointed out by Alexiadou (2001) and the references therein.

  27. Mateo Pedro (2009) argues that nominalization in Q’anjob’al and other Mayan languages requires the intransitivization of a verb, though I will propose a different analysis of Q’anjob’al in Sect. 3.1.

  28. Another crucial aspect of Alexiadou’s analysis is that many nominative-accusative languages display an ergative pattern in the realm of nominalization in the sense that the subject of transitive nominalizations is distinctly marked (e.g., by), whereas the object of transitive nominalizations and the subject of intransitive nominalizations are marked the same way (e.g., of). As mentioned in Sect. 2.3, I contend that (at least) the ergative languages discussed in the paper are ergative throughout, and the split arises simply because of structural differences, following Laka (2006) and Coon (2010a, 2013a). I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  29. Given that the external argument appears inside VoiceP, which is structurally lower than vP, in our analysis, the selection in question is non-local. I conjecture that v, which selects VoiceP, has some form of features that enable n to select the right type of VoiceP, although I leave a particular analysis of it for further research. I thank Julie Anne Legate for helpful discussion on this issue.

  30. It is relevant to note that the transitive verb inside the relative clause (= b’än) need not carry a set A marker cross-referencing its subject (= ri a Juan) in this context, according to one of the consultants. Further work is necessary on this optionality.

  31. In some instances, the unergative verb atin ‘bathe’ may carry a set A marker, which appears to suggest that an external argument appears within the nominalized clause: e.g., w-atin-ïk. However, I suspect that this use involves a simple noun but not a nominalization; it does not contain argument structure (Grimshaw 1990). In fact, w-atin-ïk may be interpreted as ‘my shower.’ Alternatively, the base of w-atin-ïk could be analyzed as undergoing causativization in the sense of Levin and Rappaport Hovav (1995) and hence acting as a transitive verb just like a transitive use of bathe in English. In this case, the set A marker found in w-atin-ïk cross-references the internal argument. It could thus be translated as ‘bathing me.’ I leave it for further research why atin behaves differently from other unergative verbs in this respect.

  32. I thank Julie Anne Legate for helpful discussion on this point.

  33. In Coon’s analysis, transitive v, which is optionally realized by the suffix in root transitives (when no overt absolutive morphology is present), assigns absolutive Case to the object in a nominalized clause.

  34. Coon posits a layered nominal projection for nominalized verbs in which there is a control relation between the subject and PRO: the subject appears in a high position of the nominal projection (i.e., Spec-PossP) and PRO occupies a Spec-vP because v requires a subject under Coon’s analysis. She argues for the highly articulated projection of a nominal domain in order to capture the parallelism between DP and CP in terms of word order (see Coon 2010a, 2013a for details.). While I assume the structure in (72) for consistency with the analysis of Kaqchikel, nothing hinges on this choice.

  35. While the set A marker on nominalized transitives of Chol (and Q’anjob’al) could be analyzed as (inherent) ergative assigned by transitive v (see Sect. 2.4.3 for details), I propose that set A markers such as the ones in (60) are genitive assigned by the D of the nominalized clause for consistency with the analysis of nominalized intransitives. For this purpose, I posit that n selects for transitive v with no inherent ergative Case in the case of nominalized transitives.

  36. This analysis can capture the fact that a preposition does not appear in non-perfective clauses of Chol, in contrast to Kaqchikel. As will be argued below, the function of the preposition chi found in progressive sentences of Kaqchikel is to Case-license its complement. The absence of a preposition in non-perfective sentences of Chol follows if choñkol Case-licenses its complement (= a nominalized clause).

  37. I suspect that the set A marker appears on D1 after Case assignment and is pronounced together with the relational noun perhaps because it is a bound morpheme. However, I leave an analysis of how and where the agreement morpheme is realized in the structure for further research, as it will go beyond the scope of the paper (see Imanishi 2014 for relevant discussion).

  38. A word is in order regarding the thematic structure of aspectual predicates found in the accusative side of Kaqchikel and Chol. The aspectual predicate choñkol found in sentences such as (60) does not assign an agentive θ-role to the subject, while its Kaqchikel counterpart ajin, which embeds a non-finite nominalized clause and a regular nominal, does: choñkol in examples such as (60) arguably assigns a theme θ-role to the nominalized clause. However, one also has to assume that Chol has another class of choñkol which has an agentive θ-role. This type of choñkol is necessary to explain constructions called B-Constructions (Coon 2010a, 2013a). These constructions require an agentive/volitional interpretation of the subject, just as in the Kaqchikel progressive sentences formed with ajin and a nominalized clause (see the references for more discussion).

  39. I assume that there is another class of ajin in the language which assigns a non-agentive/volitional θ-role to its argument. This type of ajin is necessary to capture the meaning of sentences such as (97). I also assume that what type of phrases each class of ajin selects for is defined by their subcategorization (see fn. 46 for more discussion).

  40. Here I do not assume a movement analysis of control such as Hornstein (1999).

  41. I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this line of analysis.

  42. The question might arise as to whether the θ-criterion is violated if an external θ-role of the nominalized verb in Kaqchikel as well as that of the verb in relative clauses of Polynesian languages is not assigned to any DP. While I cannot provide a definitive answer to this issue at the moment, there may be at least two possibilities. One option would be to adopt a weakened θ-criterion similar to the one proposed by Williams (1987) in which unassigned θ-roles are tolerated. Alternatively, one would allow semantic control to pass the external θ-role of the embedded verb to its controller (= the matrix subject) in one way or another. In this case, too, we would need some form of a relaxed θ-criterion, which permits a single DP to bear more than one θ-role. This form of the θ-criterion has been deemed necessary by works such as Manzini and Roussou (2000) (see also Chomsky 1986).

  43. Unlike in Kaqchikel, unaccusative verbs in Chol may be nominalized and display the same alignment pattern as unergative verbs in non-perfective sentences (Coon 2010a, 2013a). This could be captured by assuming that the type of semantic control proposed for the accusative side of Kaqchikel is not at work in non-perfective sentences of Chol (see below for relevant discussion).

  44. I am grateful to Julie Anne Legate for helpful discussion.

  45. When ajin embeds a finite clause as in (93a), I assume that semantic control is not involved. Given that the finite verb n-ø-tzaq in (93a) agrees in person and number with the subject unlike in nominalized intransitive clauses such as (91), I suggest that pro appears in the embedded clause and receives a theme θ-role from tzaq (see fn. 6 for the example with overt agreement): this seems a reasonable option since Mayan languages are pro-drop languages. In (93a), pro is simply co-referential with the overt subject that independently receives a θ-role in the matrix clause.

  46. As I suggested in fn. 39, the type of ajin found in (97) assigns a non-agentive/volitional θ-role to its argument. As pointed out by Julie Anne Legate, the present analysis would predict that this type of ajin can occur with nominalized unaccusatives unlike in examples such as (92) and (94). Given that this type of ajin does not take an agentive argument, it will not require an agentive θ-role inside the nominalization. A preliminary investigation suggests that the unaccusative example as shown below is degraded, though it is not completely ungrammatical.

    1. (ii)
      figure by

    I posit that the variant of ajin with a non-agentive/volitional θ-role can only select for a simple noun, but not a nominalized verb, whereas the one with an agentive/volitional θ-role can select for both types of nouns. However, this issue deserves further investigation. Related to this, the alignment pattern found in example (ii) resembles the one found in the accusative side of Chol and Q’anjob’al. According to Law et al. (2006), while two alignment types of the accusative side involving nominalization (= the Kaqchikel-type and the Chol/Q’anjob’al-type) do not coexist in many Mayan languages, they do in several languages as part of language change (see also Robertson 1980): Poqomchi is one of these languages. The Kaqchikel-type alignment where nominalization and a preposition are found is an archaic pattern, which was extant in Common Mayan (Robertson 1980; Law et al. 2006). As Law et al. suggest, by contrast, the Chol/Q’anjob’al-type alignment innovated in that it lost the preposition and the marking of the subject on the aspectual predicate (= raising in their term).

  47. My Kaqchikel consultants do not accept nominalized patterns as in (100). This is presumably because of dialectal differences.

  48. The present analysis would predict that the external argument cannot appear inside the nominalized verb in (100) due to the RON: the example with a set A marker cross-referencing the external argument on the nominalized verb should be ungrammatical. However, as pointed out above, nominalizations with the antipassive morpheme are not available in the dialect of Kaqchikel examined in the paper. Thus, investigation of the prediction must await further research on other dialects of Kaqchikel. I thank Julie Anne Legate for pointing this out.

  49. A similar type of nominalization can be found in other Mayan languages such as Tz’utujil (Dayley 1985), K’ichee’ (Larsen 1988; Can Pixabaj 2009) and Chol (Coon 2010a, 2013a).

  50. In Kaqchikel, number agreement and especially plural agreement may be optional for inanimate nouns; plural agreement appears to be sometimes optional for some animate nouns as well in Kaqchikel (see England 2011 for optional plural agreement in some Eastern Mayan languages).

  51. For instance, Massam (2001, 2009) observes that the transitive subject in sentences involving pseudo noun incorporation of the object in Niuean (= an ergative language) bears the absolutive marker, but not the ergative marker, just as in intransitive sentences.

  52. One of the peculiar properties of pseudo noun incorporation in Niuean is that the incorporated material can be phrasal: e.g., nouns may be modified by adjectives (Massam 2001). In contrast, regular incorporated nouns in other languages may not be phrasal but must be a head (Baker 1988, 2009).

  53. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for helpful discussion.

References

  • Abney, Steven. 1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Aissen, Judith. 1992. Topic and focus in Mayan. Language 68 (1): 43–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldridge, Edith. 2004. Ergativity and word order in Austronesian languages. PhD diss., Cornell University.

  • Aldridge, Edith. 2008. Generative approaches to ergativity. Language and Linguistic Compass: Syntax and Morphology 2: 966–995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis. 2001. Functional structure in nominals: Nominalization and ergativity. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexiadou, Artemis, Liliane Haegeman, and Melita Stavrou. 2007. Noun phrase in the generative perspective. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anand, Pranav, and Andrew Nevins. 2006. The locus of ergative case assignment: Evidence from scope. In Ergativity: Emerging issues, eds. Diane Massam and Juvenal Ndayiragije, 3–25. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Stephen R. 1976. On the notion of subject in ergative languages. In Subject and topic, ed. Charles Li, 1–23. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark C. 1988. Incorporation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark C. 2009. Is head movement still needed for noun incorporation? Lingua 119: 148–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark C. 2014. On dependent ergative case (in Shipibo) and its derivation by phase. Linguistic Inquiry 45 (3): 341–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark C. 2015. Case: Its principles and its parameters. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark C., and Nadya Vinokurova. 2009. On agent nominalizations and why they are not like event nominalizations. Language 85 (3): 517–556.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berinstein, Ava. 1985. Evidence for multiattachment in K’ekchi Mayan. New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittner, Maria, and Kenneth Hale. 1996a. Ergativity: Toward a theory of a heterogeneous class. Linguistic Inquiry 27 (4): 531–604.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittner, Maria, and Kenneth Hale. 1996b. The structural determination of case and agreement. Linguistic Inquiry 27 (1): 1–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobaljik, Jonathan David, and Phil Branigan. 2006. Eccentric agreement and multiple Case checking. In Ergativity: Emerging issues, eds. Alana Johns, Diane Massam, and Juvenal Ndayiragije, 47–77. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bok-Bennema, Reineke. 1991. Case and agreement in Inuit. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borer, Hagit. 1984. Parametric syntax: Case studies in Semitic and Romance languages. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borsley, Robert D., and Jaklin Kornfilt. 2000. Mixed extended projections. In Syntax and semantics: The nature and function of syntactic categories, ed. Robert D. Borsley, Vol. 32, 101–131. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bošković, Željko. 2002. A-movement and the EPP. Syntax 5 (3): 167–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, Victoria R. 1977. Pronominal inflection in the Mayan languages. Occasional paper 1. New Orleans: Middle American Research Institute at Tulane University and the Zemurray Foundation.

  • Bricker, Victoria. 1981. The source of the ergative split in Yucatec Maya. Journal of Mayan Linguistics 2: 83–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, McKenna R., Judith M. Maxwell, and Walter E. Little. 2006. La ütz awäch? Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burzio, Luigi. 1986. Italian syntax. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, Lyle, and Terrence Kaufman. 1985. Mayan linguistics: Where are we now? Annual Review of Anthropology 14: 187–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Can Pixabaj, Telma Angelina. 2009. Morphosyntactic features and behaviors of verbal nouns in K’ichee’. Master’s thesis, University of Texas at Austin.

  • Carnie, Andrew. 2011. Mixed categories in Irish. Lingua 121: 1207–1224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 1984. Anaphoric properties of infinitives and gerunds. In West Coast Conference on General Linguistics (WCCFL) 3, eds. Mark Cobler, Susannah MacKaye, and Michael T. Wescoat, 28–39. Stanford: Stanford Linguistics Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on nominalization. In Readings in English transformational grammar, eds. Roderick A. Jacobs and Peter S. Rosenbaum, 184–221. Waltham: Ginn and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Knowledge of language. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Step by step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, eds. Martin Roger, David Michaels, and Juan Uriagereka, 89–155. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. Michael Kenstowicz, 1–52. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clemens, Lauren Eby. 2013. Kaqchikel SVO: V2 in a V1 language. In Studies in Kaqchikel grammar, ed. Michael Kenstowicz. Cambridge: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics (MITWPL).

    Google Scholar 

  • Clemens, Lauren Eby, and Maria Polinsky. 2017. Verb-initial word orders, 2nd edn. In The Blackwell companion to syntax, eds. Martin Everaert and Henk van Riemsdijk. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comrie, Bernard. 1976. Aspect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comrie, Bernard. 1978. Ergativity. In Syntactic typology: Studies in the phenomenology of language, 329–394. Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coon, Jessica. 2010a. Complementation in Chol (Mayan): A theory of split ergativity. PhD diss., MIT, Cambridge.

  • Coon, Jessica. 2010b. VOS as predicate fronting in Chol. Lingua 120 (2): 354–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coon, Jessica. 2013a. Aspects of split ergativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coon, Jessica. 2013b. TAM split ergativity. Language and Linguistics Compass 7 (3): 171–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coon, Jessica, Pedro Mateo Pedro, and Omer Preminger. 2011. The role of Case in A-bar extraction asymmetries: Evidence from Mayan. Manuscript.

  • Coon, Jessica, Pedro Mateo Pedro, and Omer Preminger. 2014. The role of Case in A-bar extraction asymmetries: Evidence from Mayan. Linguistic Variation 14 (2): 179–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayley, Jon. 1981. Voice and ergativity in Mayan languages. Journal of Mayan Linguistics 2: 3–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayley, Jon P. 1985. Tzutujil grammar. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeChicchis, Joseph. 1989. Q’eqchi’ (Kekchi Mayan) variation in Guatemala and Belize. PhD diss., University of Pennsylvania.

  • Dixon, R. M. W. 1979. Ergativity. Language 55: 59–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, R. M. W. 1994. Ergativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • England, Nora C. 1983a. Ergativity in Mamean (Mayan) languages. International Journal of American Linguistics 49: 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • England, Nora C. 1983b. A grammar of Mam, a Mayan language. Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • England, Nora C. 1991. Changes in basic word order in Mayana languages. International Journal of American Linguistics 57: 446–486.

    Google Scholar 

  • England, Nora C. 2003. Mayan language revival and revitalization politics: Linguists and linguistic ideologies. American Anthropologist 105 (4): 733–743.

    Google Scholar 

  • England, Nora C. 2011. Plurality agreement in some eastern Mayan languages. International Journal of American Linguistics 77 (3): 397–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erlewine, Michael Yoshitaka. 2016. Anti-locality and optimality in Kaqchikel Agent Focus. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 34 (2): 429–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny, and David Pesetsky. 2005. Cyclic linearization of syntactic structure. Theoretical Linguistics 31: 1–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fu, Jingqi, Thomas Roeper, and Hagit Borer. 2001. The VP withing process nominals: Evidence from adverbs and the VP anaphor do-so. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19 (3): 549–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukui, Naoki. 1986. A theory of category projection and its applications. PhD diss., MIT.

  • García Matzar, Lolmay Pedro Oscar. 2007. Rujotayixik tzij pa Kaqchikel: Derivación de palabras en Kaqchikel. Guatemala: OKMA.

    Google Scholar 

  • García Matzar, Lolmay Pedro, and José Obispo Rodríguez Guaján. 1997. Rukemik ri Kaqchikel Chi’: Gramática Kaqchikel. Guatemala City: Cholsamaj.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimshaw, Jane. 1990. Argument strucuture. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimshaw, Jane. 1991. Extended projection. Ms., Brandeis University.

  • Hale, Kenneth, and Samuel Jay Keyser. 1993. On argument structure and the lexical expression of syntactic relations. In The view from building 20, eds. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, 53–110. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harley, Heidi. 2013. External arguments and the mirror principle: On the distinctness of Voice and v. Lingua 125: 34–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herd, Jonathon, Catherine Macdonald, and Diane Massam. 2011. Genitive subjects in relative constructions in Polynesian languages. Lingua 121: 1252–1264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornstein, Norbert. 1999. Movement and control. Linguistic Inquiry 30 (1): 69–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Imanishi, Yusuke. 2014. Default ergative. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Imanishi, Yusuke, and Pedro Mateo Pedro. 2013. Deriving nominals in Kaqchikel. In Studies in Kaqchikel grammar, ed. Michael Kenstowicz, 51–66. Cambridge: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics (MITWPL).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornfilt, Jaklin, and John Whitman. 2011. Afterword: Nominalizations in syntactic theory. Lingua 121: 1297–1313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Phrase structure and the lexicon, eds. Johan Rooryck and Laurie Zaring, 109–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laka, Itziar. 2006. Deriving split ergativity in the progressive: The case of Basque. In Ergativity: Emerging issues, eds. Alana Johns, Diane Massam, and Juvenal Ndayiragije, 173–195. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, Thomas W. 1981. Functional correlates of ergativity in Aguatec. In Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (BLS) 7, 136–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, Thomas W. 1988. Manifestations of ergativity in Quiché grammar. PhD diss., University of California, Berkeley.

  • Larsen, Thomas W., and William M. Norman. 1979. Correlates of ergativity in Mayan grammar. In Ergativity: Towards a theory of grammatical relations, ed. Frans Plank, 347–370. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Law, Danny, John Robertson, and Stephen Houston. 2006. Split ergativity in the history of the Ch’olan branch of the Mayan language family. International Journal of American Linguistics 72: 415–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legate, Julie Anne. 2002. Warlpiri: Theoretical implications. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Legate, Julie Anne. 2008. Morphological and abstract case. Linguistic Inquiry 39: 55–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legate, Julie Anne. 2014. Voice and v: Lessons from Acehnese. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lengyel, Thomas E. 1978. Ergativity, aspect and related perplexities of Ixil-Maya. In Papers in Mayan linguistics, ed. Nora C. England, 78–91. Columbia: University of Missouri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth, and Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity: At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macario, Narciso Cojti, Martin Chacach Cutzal, and Marcos Armando Cali. 1998. Diccionario Kaqchikel. La Antigua, Guatemala: Cholsamaj.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, Rita M., and Anna Roussou. 2000. A minimalist theory of A-movement and control. Lingua 110: 409–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. In 21st Annual Penn Linguistics Colloquium (PLC). Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 4.2., 201–225. Philadelphia: Penn Linguistics Club.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massam, Diane. 2001. Pseudo noun incorporation in Niuean. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19: 153–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massam, Diane. 2006. Neither absolutive nor ergative is nominative or accusative: Arguments from Niuean. In Ergativity: Emerging issues, eds. Alana Johns, Diane Massam, and Juvenal Ndayiragije, 27–46. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massam, Diane. 2009. Noun incorporation: Essentials and extensions. Language and Linguistics Compass 3: 1076–1096.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateo Pedro, Pedro. 2009. Nominalization in Q’anjob’al (Maya). In Kansas Working Papers in Linguistics, 46–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateo Pedro, Pedro. 2010. The acquisition of verb inflection in Q’anjob’al Maya: A longitudinal study. PhD diss., University of Kansas.

  • Mateo Pedro, Pedro. 2011. Revisiting split ergativity in Q’anjob’al. In Semantics of Under-represented Languages in the Americas (SULA) 5, ed. Suzi Lima. Amherst: University of Massachusetts GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateo Toledo, B’alam Eladio. 2003. Ergatividad mixta en Q’anjobal (Maya): Un reanálisis. In Conference of Indigenous Language of Latin America 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateo Toledo, B’alam Eladio. 2008. The family of complex predicates in Q’anjob’al (Maya): Their syntax and meaning. PhD diss, The University of Texas at Austin.

  • Maxwell, Judith M., and Robert M. Hill. 2006. Kaqchikel chronicles. Austin: University of Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinnis, Martha. 2004. Lethal ambiguity. Linguistic Inquiry 35 (1): 47–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mithun, Marianne. 1984. The evolution of noun incorporation. Language 60 (4): 847–894.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, Edith A. 1978. On the distribution of ergative and accusative patterns. Lingua 45: 233–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murasugi, Kumiko. 1992. Crossing and nested paths: NP movement in accusative and ergative languages. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Nichols, Johanna. 1986. Head-marking and dependent-marking grammar. Language 62 (1): 56–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patal Majtzul, Filiberto. 2007. Rusoltzil ri Kaqchikel: Diccionario bilingüe estándar Kaqchikel illustrado. Guatemala: OKMA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polinsky, Maria. 2011. Antipassive constructions. In The world atlas of language structures online, eds. Matthew Dryer and Martin Haspelmath. Munich: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology. Chap. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Portner, Paul. 1992. Situation theory and the semantics of propositional expressions. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Preminger, Omer. 2011. Agreement as a fallible operation. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Preminger, Omer. 2014. Agreement and its failures. Linguistic inquiry monographs. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, John S. 1980. The structure of pronoun incorporation in the Mayan verbal complex. New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salanova, Andrès Pablo. 2007. Nominalizations and aspect. PhD diss., MIT, Cambridge, MA.

  • Shklovsky, Kirill. 2012. Tseltal clause structure. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Silverstein, Michael. 1976. Hierarchies of features and ergativity. In Grammatical categories in Australian languages, ed. R. M. W. Dixon, 112–171. New Jersey: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tada, Hiroaki. 1993. A/A-bar partition in derivation. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Tsunoda, Tasaku. 1981. Split case-marking patterns in verb types and tense/aspect/mood. Linguistics 19: 389–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ura, Hiroyuki. 2000. Checking theory and grammatical functions in Universal Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ura, Hiroyuki. 2001. Case. In The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, eds. Mark Baltin and Chris Collins, 334–373. Malden: Blackwell Sci.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vázquez Álvarez, Juan J. 2011. A grammar of Chol, a Mayan language. PhD diss., University of Texas at Austin.

  • Vergnaud, Jean-Roger. 1976/2006. Letter to Noam Chomsky and Howard Lasnik. Syntax: Critical concepts in linguistics, eds. Robert Freidin and Howard Lasnik, Vol. 5, 21–34. London: Routledge.

  • Williams, Edwin. 1987. Implicit arguments, the binding theory, and control. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 5 (2): 151–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolford, Ellen. 2006. Lexical case, inherent case, and argument structure. Linguistic Inquiry 37: 111–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wurmbrand, Susi. 2002. Syntactic versus semantic control. In Studies in comparative Germanic syntax: Proceedings of the 15th workshop on comparative Germanic syntax, eds. Jan Wouter Zwart and Werner Abraham, 93–127. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yasugi, Yoshiho. 1995. Native Middle American languages: An areal-typological perspective. Senri: National Museum of Ethnology.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to my Kaqchikel consultants, Alberto Sipac Aju, Ana López de Mateo and Anacleto Catú, for their assistance with my fieldwork research and patience, without which this research would have been impossible. I am very grateful to the anonymous reviewers for NLLT, Jessica Coon, Sabine Iatridou, Hideki Kishimoto, Julie Anne Legate, Pedro Mateo Pedro, David Pesetsky, Masha Polinsky and Norvin Richards for their invaluable feedback and helpful suggestions. Special thanks to Julie Anne Legate for her editorial assistance and numerous helpful suggestions. I would also like to thank the audiences at WCCFL 32, the colloquia at Keio University and Kobe University, and Morphology and Lexicon Forum at Konan University. Unless otherwise noted, the Kaqchikel data are drawn from my field notes. Any shortcomings or errors in the data or analysis are my own. This research has been funded by MIT’s Ken Hale Fund for Fieldwork Research, the JSPS Grant-in-Aid for Young Scientists (B) (No.15K16752) and the JSPS Grant-in-Aid for Young Scientists (18K12388).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yusuke Imanishi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Imanishi, Y. Parameterizing split ergativity in Mayan. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 38, 151–200 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-09440-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-018-09440-9

Keywords

Navigation