Abstract
I examine the abstraction/representation theory of computation put forward by Horsman et al., connecting it to the broader notion of modeling, and in particular, model-based explanation, as considered by Rosen. I argue that the ‘representational entities’ it depends on cannot themselves be computational, and that, in particular, their representational capacities cannot be realized by computational means, and must remain explanatorily opaque to them. I then propose that representation might be realized by subjective experience (qualia), through being the bearer of the structure of abstract objects that are represented.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.


References
Block, N. (1980). Troubles with functionalism. Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, 1, 268–305.
Boolos, G. S., & Jeffrey, R. C. (1989). Computability and logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bringsjord, S., & Zenzen, M. (2003). Superminds: People harness hypercomputation, and more (Vol. 29). Berlin: Springer Science & Business Media.
Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Carruthers, P. (2007). Higher-order theories of consciousness. The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 288–297). Oxford: Blackwell.
Chaitin, G. (2006). The limits of reason. Scientific American, 294(3), 74–81.
Chalmers, D. J. (1994). On implementing a computation. Minds and Machines, 4(4), 391–402.
Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of consciousness studies, 2(3), 200–219.
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Church, A. (1932). A set of postulates for the foundation of logic. Annals of Mathematics, 33, 346–366.
Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Copeland, B. J., & Proudfoot, D. (1999). Alan Turing’s forgotten ideas in computer science. Scientific American, 280(4), 98–103.
Cubitt, T. S., Perez-Garcia, D., & Wolf, M. M. (2015). Undecidability of the spectral gap. Nature, 528(7581), 207.
de Oliveira, G.S. (2018). Representationalism is a dead end. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01995-9
Demopoulos, W., & Friedman, M. (1985). Bertrand Russell’s the analysis of matter: Its historical context and contemporary interest. Philosophy of Science, 52(4), 621–639.
Dennett, D. C. (1988). Quining qualia. In Bisiach, E. & Marcel, A. (Eds.), Consciousness in modern science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eddington, A. (1928). The nature of the physical world. New York: Macmillan.
Enderton, H. (2001). A mathematical introduction to logic. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Harvard: Harvard University Press.
Fuchs, C. A. (2017). On participatory realism. Information and interaction (pp. 113–134). Berlin: Springer.
Gödel, K. (1931). Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38(1), 173–198.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Triviality arguments against functionalism. Philosophical Studies, 145(2), 273–295.
Hameroff, S. R., & Penrose, R. (2017). Consciousness in the universe: An updated review of the “Orch-OR” theory of consciousness. In J. A. Tuszynski, T. E. Feinberg, & R. R. Poznanski (Eds.), A foundational approach, biophysics of consciousness (pp. 517–599). Singapore: World Scientific.
Horsman, C., Stepney, S., Wagner, R. C., & Kendon, V. (2014). When does a physical system compute? Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 470(2169), 20140182.
Horsman, D. C. (2015). Abstraction/representation theory for heterotic physical computing. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 373(2046), 20140224.
Horsman, D., Kendon, V., Stepney, S., & Young, J. P. W. (2017). Abstraction and representation in living organisms: When does a biological system compute? Representation and reality in humans, other living organisms and intelligent machines (pp. 91–116). Berlin: Springer.
Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 32(127), 127–136.
James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, 9(34), 188–205.
Kenny, A. J. (1971). The homunculus fallacy. In M. Grene & I. Prigogine (Eds.), Interpretations of life and mind: Essays around the problem of reduction (pp. 65–74). London: Routledge.
Kim, J. (1987). “Strong” and “Global” supervenience revisited. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 48(2), 315–326.
Kleene, S. C. (1943). Recursive predicates and quantifiers. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 53(1), 41–73.
Kleene, S. C. (1952). Introduction to metamathematics. New York: van Nordstrand.
Klein, C. (2008). Dispositional implementation solves the superfluous structure problem. Synthese, 165(1), 141–153.
Kriegel, U. (2003). The new mysterianism and the thesis of cognitive closure. Acta Analytica, 18(30–31), 177–191.
Kriegel, U. (2009). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kriegel, U., & Williford, K. (Eds.). (2006). Self-representational approaches to consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Lange, C. G. (1887). Über Gemütsbewegungen (Org.Om Sindsbevægelser). Leipzig: Thomas Theodor.
Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(4), 354–361.
Lycan, W. G. (1981). Form, function, and feel. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(1), 24–50.
Lycan, W. G. (2015). Representational theories of consciousness. Metaphysics research lab. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, summer 2015 ed. Stanford: Stanford University.
Miller, F. (1882). Telegraphic code to insure privacy and secrecy in the transmission of telegrams. New York: CM Cornwell.
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.
Newman, M. H. (1928). Mr. Russell’s “Causal Theory of Perception”. Mind, 37(146), 137–148.
Paterek, T., Kofler, J., Prevedel, R., Klimek, P., Aspelmeyer, M., Zeilinger, A., et al. (2010). Logical independence and quantum randomness. New Journal of Physics, 12(1), 013019.
Peres, A., & Zurek, W. H. (1982). Is quantum theory universally valid? American Journal of Physics, 50(9), 807–810.
Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Putnam, H. (1960). Minds and machines. In S. Hook (Ed.), Dimensions of mind: A symposium (pp. 138–164). New York: Collier.
Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. Cambridge: MIT press.
Rice, H. G. (1953). Classes of recursively enumerable sets and their decision problems. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 74(2), 358–366.
Robič, B. (2015). The foundations of computability theory. Berlin: Springer.
Rogers, H. (1967). Theory of recursive functions and effective computability (Vol. 5). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Rosen, R. (1991). Life itself: A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.
Russell, B. (1927). The analysis of matter. London: Routledge.
Seager, W. (2006). The ‘Intrinsic Nature’ argument for panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10–11), 129–145.
Seager, W. (2016). Theories of consciousness: an introduction (2nd ed.). Abingdon: Routledge.
Searle, J. R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge: MIT press.
Shagrir, O. (2006). Why we view the brain as a computer. Synthese, 153(3), 393–416.
Shagrir, O. (2012). Computation, implementation, cognition. Minds and Machines, 22(2), 137–148.
Shoemaker, S. (1982). The inverted spectrum. The Journal of Philosophy, 79(7), 357–381.
Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10/11), 3.
Strawson, G. (2019). What does “physical” mean? a prolegomenon to physicalist panpsychism. In W. Seager (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of panpsychism. Abingdon: Routledge.
Szangolies, J. (2015). Von Neumann minds: Intentional automata. Mind Matter, 13(2), 169–191.
Szangolies, J. (2018a). Epistemic horizons and the foundations of quantum mechanics. Foundations of Physics, 48(12), 1669–1697.
Szangolies, J. (2018b). Von Neumann minds: A toy model of meaning in a natural world. In B. Foster, Z. Merali, & A. Aguirre (Eds.), Wandering towards a goal (pp. 29–39). Berlin: Springer.
Tetens, H. (2013). Wissenschaftstheorie: Eine Einführung, vol 2808. CH Beck.
Turing, A. M. (1937). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 2(1), 230–265.
von Neumann, J. (1966). The theory of automata: construction, reproduction, homogeneity, original unpublished manuscript, 1952–1953. In A. W. Burke (Ed.), Theory of self-reproducing automata (pp. 91–381). Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Whitehead, A. N. (1925). Science and the modern world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Yanofsky, N. S. (2003). A universal approach to self-referential paradoxes, incompleteness and fixed points. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 9(3), 362–386.
Zwick, M. (1978). Quantum measurement and Gödel’s proof. Speculations in Science and Technology, 1(2), I978.
Acknowledgements
I warmly thank Peter Hankins and two anonymous referees for comments and criticism on earlier versions of many of the arguments presented here.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Szangolies, J. The Abstraction/Representation Account of Computation and Subjective Experience. Minds & Machines 30, 259–299 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-020-09522-x
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-020-09522-x