Skip to main content
Log in

Ethical signposts for clinical geneticists in secondary variant and incidental finding disclosure discussions

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While ethical and empirical interest in so-called secondary variants and incidental findings in clinical genetics contexts is growing, critical reflection on the ethical foundations of the various recommendations proposed is thus far largely lacking. We examine and critique the ethical justifications of the three most prominent disclosure positions: briefly, the clinical geneticist decides, a joint decision, and the patient decides. Subsequently, instead of immediately developing a new disclosure option, we explore relevant foundational ethical values and norms, drawing on the normative and empirical ethical literature. Four ethical signposts are thereby developed to help guide disclosure discussions. These are: respectful sharing of the clinician’s expertise; transparent communication; epistemic modesty; and respect for the embedded nature of the patient. We conclude by considering the most common current disclosure positions in the light of the four ethical signposts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that we consistently use the term ‘genetic test’ (/’genetic testing’) throughout this paper, because of the focus on genetics contexts and geneticists. However, we are mainly referring to genomic tests, exomic tests, or tests that target a panel of genes. These tests utilise techniques such as array-comparative genomic hybridisation (array-CGH) and next generation sequencing (NGS). These techniques are increasingly being used in clinical contexts instead of older genetic techniques, and are more likely to generate SVs/IFs than previous techniques.

  2. For example, in 2013 the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (ACMG) published recommendations for the reporting of SVs/IFs in clinical exome and genome sequencing. The recommendations included a “minimum list” of secondary variants that laboratories should always seek and report to clinicians, whenever clinical sequencing is carried out. Secondary variants were admitted to the list if they were able to be confirmed by other diagnostic methods and were medically actionable based on current evidence and the clinical consensus of the authors of the recommendations. Such clinical consensus can be difficult to obtain, as evidenced by an article written by the same authors of the recommendations (cf. Green et al. 2012). Agreeing upon a list of secondary variants is thus still a work in progress.

  3. Taking the example of the list of secondary variants developed by the ACMG (endnote 2), their decisions were based on medical factors (verifiability and medical actionability of the variant), rooted in the ethical norm of the clinical duty to promote the wellbeing of patients.

  4. ‘Clinical utility’ can be defined as the likelihood that knowing the result will effect a positive change in clinical management, ending in net benefit for the patient (Cf. Sanderson et al. 2005).

  5. This is also true in research contexts (cf. Bredenoord et al. 2011a).

  6. ‘Actionability’ refers to whether knowing a result will lead to or enable some sort of action. For example, knowing that one harbours a mutation related to colon cancer is ‘actionable’ because there are certain preventive measures available such as increased screening; it is debatable whether knowing that one harbours a mutation related to Alzheimer’s disease is actionable, because there are no prevention or early treatment options available. ‘Clinical validity’ refers to the ability of the genetic result to predict that particular condition (Cf. Sanderson et al. 2005). Some results can be clinically valid without having clinical utility; other results might have neither clinical validity nor clinical utility, if the clinical consequences are unknown.

  7. For example, the oft-cited “binning method” for IFs developed by Berg et al. relies solely on clinically defined criteria (cf. Berg et al. 2011). A recent so-called ‘novel method’ for evaluating IFs for disclosure also bases itself heavily on clinically defined criteria, to the exclusion of other criteria (cf. Goddard et al. 2013). An alternative way of judging SVs/IFs would be to make room for other factors that might also be important for patients, such as the potential impact of the disease and the financial cost (cf. Bennette et al. 2013).

  8. We acknowledge that what follows is based on a relatively unsophisticated view of utilitarianism, emphasising utility and net benefit; this is all that is needed for the purposes of our argument. For a more detailed discussion (cf. e.g. Driver 2009).

  9. Cf. the results of two recent qualitative studies on the views of parents regarding the disclosure of SVs/IFs (Christenhusz et al. 2014 and Driessnack et al.). Many participants showed an openness to the ambiguities of life and a more integrated view of the potential impact of a given SV/IF than the concept of “net benefit” would seem to allow.

  10. For example, solidarity and relationality have entered the ethical debate on genetic and genomic issues in discussions on whether individuals might have a duty to share relevant, beneficial genetic results with their family members and partners.

  11. The “dynamic consent” model is one attempt to realise the process nature of consent practically (cf. Kaye et al. 2014). Dynamic consent utilises a personalised, digital communication interface between researchers and participants. The aim is participants who will be more engaged, informed and scientifically literate and thus able to tailor and manage their own consent and return of results (including SVs/IFs) preferences. Developed in biobanking contexts, it has application potential in other domains such as the clinic. It remains to be seen whether digital communication is a sufficient substitute for face-to-face contact especially in clinical contexts, or whether the two forms could be combined.

  12. Principlism has received so much critique over the years that this hardly needs repeating here.

  13. Moreover, autonomous choice can only be expressed fully in a society in which the consequences of that choice are possible. For example, there is something lacking in the autonomous choice to be tested for the BRCA1 mutation associated with an increased risk of breast and ovarian cancer, if the recommended prevention strategies of increased screening and a prophylactic mastectomy are unavailable in one’s country. It must be acknowledged that the present article has been written from a Western perspective, in which the medical actionability of at least some SVs/IFs is a ready possibility.

  14. For example, the question of whether it is just to devote public resources to the increased follow-up costs of genetic tests conducted on individuals.

  15. A typical pleiotropic association is the ApoE gene; mutations in this gene are associated with increased risk of cardiac disease and Alzheimer’s disease.

  16. A form of non-coercive paternalism that involves presenting a range of options in such a way that people are more likely to choose what will most enhance their welfare. A similar, earlier concept is ‘informative paternalism’ (cf. Nikku 1997).

  17. Clinical validity and clinical utility have been defined above (endnotes 4 and 6). ‘Analytic validity,’ as defined by Sanderson et al., refers to how accurately and reliably a given genetic test identifies a certain genotype. Analytic validity is measured in a laboratory, not in a clinical setting.

  18. There are arguments in favour of limiting the number of SVs/IFs as far as possible before conducting a genomic test; e.g. Christenhusz et al. 2012. Unrestricted choice before the test is carried out can be overwhelming (cf. Bredenoord et al. 2011b; Bowdin et al. 2014). Also, information-overload through disclosing too many results runs the risk of drowning out the seriousness of the truly important findings (cf. Christensen and Green 2013).

  19. E.g. heart disease might be nothing big for one person and the end of the world for someone else. One person may explicitly desire to know an SV/IF indicating Alzheimer’s disease because their mother had it, while their sibling may explicitly not want to know because of the same experience. The ‘phenotype-meaning gap’ is analogous to the established ‘genotype-phenotype gap,’ the phenomenon that the same genetic profile can sometimes be expressed in a variety of ways, thus limiting the predictive power of genetic information.

  20. Epistemology refers to the study of knowledge. With the term “epistemic modesty” we mean to refer to a conscious acknowledgement of the limitations of knowledge and thus the limitations of what can be communicated about SVs/IFs.

  21. At this time, this clinical benefit is especially evident in their use in gene identification for unresolved genetic disorders in individuals with developmental disabilities or congenital anomalies.

  22. Although the primary finding may not always be ‘found’; i.e., some conditions may remain undiagnosed genetically.

  23. E.g. childhood, early adulthood, early career and/or family life, middle age, retirement.

  24. For example, when disclosing an SV/IF predicting Huntington’s disease in a patient who is just about to start a family, it would be appropriate to also discuss their options regarding having children. If the patient already had adult children, it would be appropriate to also discuss how they might disclose this information to their children. The varying impact of SVs/IFs at different points in the life cycle has been raised as an issue in empirical research; e.g. Christenhusz 2014.

  25. Very few genetic conditions will develop with 100 % certainty. Huntington’s disease is one of the rare examples, but even then there is the uncertainty of when it will manifest.

  26. As evidenced for example by two studies involving Dutch general practitioners, gynaecologists, paediatricians, and medical students (cf. Baars et al. 2005a, b).

References

  • Baars, M.J., L. Henneman, et al. 2005a. Deficiency of knowledge of genetics and genetic tests among general practitioners, gynecologists, and pediatricians: A global problem. Genetics in Medicine 7(9): 605–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baars, M.J., A.J. Scherpbier, et al. 2005b. Deficient knowledge of genetics relevant for daily practice among medical students nearing graduation. Genetics in Medicine 7(5): 295–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2009. The Principles of Biomedical Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennette, C.S., S.B. Trinidad, et al. 2013. Return of incidental findings in genomic medicine: Measuring what patients value—Development of an instrument to measure preferences for information from next-generation testing (IMPRINT). Genetics in Medicine 15(11): 873–881.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, J.S., M.J. Khoury, et al. 2011. Deploying whole genome sequencing in clinical practice and public health: Meeting the challenge one bin at a time. Genetics in Medicine 13(6): 499–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkman, B.E., and S.C. Hull. 2014. The “right not to know” in the genomic era: Time to break from tradition? The American Journal of Bioethics 14(3): 28–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boenink, M., and S. van der Burg. 2010. Informed decision making about predictive DNA tests: Arguments for more public visibility of personal deliberations about the good life. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13(2): 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borry, P., P. Schotsmans, et al. 2004. What is the role of empirical research in bioethical reflection and decision-making? An ethical analysis. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 7(1): 41–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowdin, S., P. Ray, et al. 2014. The genome clinic: A multidisciplinary approach to assessing the opportunities and challenges of integrating genomic analysis into clinical care. Human Mutation 35(5): 513–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bredenoord, A., H. Kroes, et al. 2011a. Disclosure of individual genetic data to research participants: The debate reconsidered. Trends in Genetics 27(2): 41–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bredenoord, A.L., N.C. Onland-Moret, et al. 2011b. Feedback of individual genetic results to research participants: In favor of a qualified disclosure policy. Human Mutation 32(8): 861–867.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christenhusz, G. M., K. Devriendt, et al. 2012. Why genomics shouldn't get too personal: In favor of filters: Re: Invited comment by Holly K. Tabor et al. in American Journal of Medical Genetics Part A Volume 155. American Journal of Medical Genetics Part A 158A: 2641-2642.

  • Christenhusz, G. M., K. Devriendt, et al. 2013a. To tell or not to tell? A systematic review of ethical reflections on incidental findings arising in genetics contexts. European Journal of Human Genetics 21: 248-255.

  • Christenhusz, G. M., K. Devriendt, et al. 2013b. Disclosing incidental findings in genetics contexts: A review of the empirical ethical research. European Journal of Medical Genetics 56(10): 529-540.

  • Christenhusz, G. M., K. Devriendt, et al. 2013c. Secondary variants: In defense of a more fitting term in the incidental findings debate. European Journal of Human Genetics 21: 1331-1334.

  • Christenhusz, G. M., K. Devriendt, et al. 2014. The communication of secondary variants: Interviews with parents whose children have undergone array-CGH testing. Clinical Genetics 86: 207-216.

  • Christenhusz, G. M. 2014. Ethical aspects of genetic testing and the return of secondary variants in the new genomic era. KU Leuven, Leuven, Belgium. 

  • Christensen, K.D., and R.C. Green. 2013. How could disclosing incidental information from whole-genome sequencing affect patient behavior? Personalized Medicine 10(4): 377–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalby, S. 1995. GIG response to the UK Clinical Genetics Society report “The genetic testing of children”. Journal of Medical Genetics 32(6): 490–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drane, J.F. 1985. The many faces of competency. Hastings Center Report 15(2): 17–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driessnack, M., S. Daack-Hirsch, et al. 2013. The disclosure of incidental genomic findings: An “ethically important moment” in pediatric research and practice. Journal of Community Genetics 4(4): 435–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2009) The history of utilitarianism. In The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/utilitarianism-history/. Accessed 17 Nov 2014.

  • Foster, M.W., J.J. Mulvihill, et al. 2009. Evaluating the utility of personal genomic information. Genetics in Medicine 11(8): 570–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goddard, K.A., E.P. Whitlock, et al. 2013. Description and pilot results from a novel method for evaluating return of incidental findings from next-generation sequencing technologies. Genetics in Medicine 15: 721–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, R.C., J.S. Berg, et al. 2012. Exploring concordance and discordance for return of incidental findings from clinical sequencing. Genetics in Medicine 14(4): 405–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, R.C., J.S. Berg, et al. 2013. ACMG recommendations for reporting of incidental findings in clinical exome and genome sequencing. Genetics in Medicine 15(7): 565–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grosse, S.D., C.M. McBride, et al. 2009. Personal utility and genomic information: Look before you leap. Genetics in Medicine 11(8): 575–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, S.G. 2006. Recognizing tacit knowledge in medical epistemology. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27(3): 187–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Juengst, E.T., M.A. Flatt, et al. 2012. Personalized genomic medicine and the rhetoric of empowerment. Hastings Center Report 42(5): 34–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kakuk, P. 2006. Genetic information in the age of genohype. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 9(3): 325–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kakuk, P. 2008. Gene concepts and genethics: Beyond exceptionalism. Science and Engineering Ethics 14(3): 357–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaut, K.P. 2006. Counseling psychology in the era of genetic testing: Considerations for practice, research, and training. The Counseling Psychologist 34(4): 461–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, J., E. A. Whitley, et al. (2014). Dynamic consent: A patient interface for twenty-first century research networks. European Journal of Human Genetics. doi:10.1038/ejhg.2014.71.

  • Knoppers, B.M., and R. Chadwick. 2005. Human genetic research: Emerging trends in ethics. Nature Reviews Genetics 6(1): 75–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kocarnik, J.M., and S.M. Fullerton. 2014. Returning pleiotropic results from genetic testing to patients and research participants. JAMA 311(8): 795–796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohane, I.S., and P.L. Taylor. 2010. Multidimensional results reporting to participants in genomic studies: Getting it right. Science Translational Medicine 2(37): 37cm19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuczewski, M.G. 1996. Reconceiving the family. The process of consent in medical decisionmaking. Hastings Center Report 26(2): 30–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. 2002. Development aid: On ontogeny and ethics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33(2): 195–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mardis, E.R. 2008. Next-generation DNA sequencing methods. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 9: 387–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBride, C.M., L.M. Koehly, et al. 2010. The behavioral response to personalized genetic information: Will genetic risk profiles motivate individuals and families to choose more healthful behaviors? Annual Review of Public Health 31: 89–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGuire, A.L., L.B. McCullough, et al. 2013. The indispensable role of professional judgment in genomic medicine. JAMA 309(14): 1465–1466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D., M. Adam, et al. 2010. Consensus statement: Chromosomal microarray is a first-tier clinical diagnostic test for individuals with developmental disabilities or congenital anomalies. American Journal of Human Genetics 86(5): 749–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, F.G., M.M. Mello, et al. 2008. Incidental findings in human subjects research: What do investigators owe research participants? The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36(2): 271–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nikku, N. 1997. Informative Paternalism. Case studies in the ethics of promoting and predicting health. Linköping: Linköpings Universitet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmboom, G., and D. Willems. 2010. Risk detection in individual health care: Any limits? Bioethics 24(8): 431–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, M., and A. Lucassen. 2004. Genetic information: A joint account? British Medical Journal 329(7458): 165–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, S.A., S.M. Laham, et al. 2013. The future in clinical genetics: Affective forecasting biases in patient and clinician decision making. Clinical Genetics 85(4): 312–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues. (2013). Anticipate and communicate: ethical management of incidental and secondary findings in the clinical, research and direct-to-consumer contexts. http://bioethics.gov/sites/default/files/FINALAnticipateCommunicate_PCSBI_0.pdf. Accessed 9 July 2014.

  • Ramos, E.M., C. Din-Lovinescu, et al. 2014. Characterizing genetic variants for clinical action. American Journal of Medical Genetics Part C: Seminars in Medical Genetics 166C(1): 93–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolland, J.S. 1987. Family illness paradigms: Evolution and significance. Family Systems Medicine 5(4): 482–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolland, J.S., and J.K. Williams. 2005. Toward a biopsychosocial model for 21st-century genetics. Family Process 44(1): 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanderson, S., R. Zimmern, et al. 2005. How can the evaluation of genetic tests be enhanced? Lessons learned from the ACCE framework and evaluating genetic tests in the United Kingdom. Genetics in Medicine 7(7): 495–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scully, J.L., R. Porz, et al. 2007. You don’t make genetic test decisions from one day to the next—Using time to preserve moral space. Bioethics 21(4): 208–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sevdalis, N., and N. Harvey. 2006. Predicting preferences: A neglected aspect of shared decision-making. Health Expectations 9(3): 245–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soldan, J., E. Street, et al. 2000. Psychological model for presymptomatic test interviews: Lessons learned from Huntington Disease. Journal of Genetic Counseling 9(1): 15–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, B.D. 2014. Incidentalomas in genomics and radiology. New England Journal of Medicine 370(11): 988–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R., and R.H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. The University of Chicago Law Review 70(4): 1159–1202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suter, S.M. 1998. Value neutrality and nondirectiveness: Comments on “Future directions in genetic counseling”. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8(2): 161–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Townsend, A., S. Adam, et al. 2012. “I want to know what’s in Pandora’s box”: Comparing stakeholder perspectives on incidental findings in clinical whole genomic sequencing. American Journal of Medical Genetics Part A 158A(10): 2519–2525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Riper, M. 2010. Genomics and the family: Integrative frameworks, 109–139. Handbook of Genomics and the Family: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wachbroit, R., and D. Wasserman. 1995. Patient autonomy and value-neutrality in nondirective genetic counseling. Stanford Law and Policy Review 6(2): 103–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, F. 2003. Family resilience: A framework for clinical practice. Family Process 42(1): 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widdows, A. 2009. Between the individual and the community: The impact of genetics on ethical models. New Genetics and Society 28(2): 173–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S.M. 2008. Introduction: The challenge of incidental findings. The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36(2): 216–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S.M., F.P. Lawrenz, et al. 2008. Managing incidental findings in human subjects research: Analysis and recommendations. The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36(2): 219–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worthey, E.A., A.N. Mayer, et al. 2011. Making a definitive diagnosis: Successful clinical application of whole exome sequencing in a child with intractable inflammatory bowel disease. Genetics in Medicine 13(3): 255–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

K. Devriendt and H. Van Esch are senior clinical investigators of the FWO-Vlaanderen and of the “Interuniversity Attraction Poles” programme of the Belgian federal scientific policy office, Project P7/43 “BeMGI.”

Conflict of interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gabrielle M. Christenhusz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Christenhusz, G.M., Devriendt, K., Van Esch, H. et al. Ethical signposts for clinical geneticists in secondary variant and incidental finding disclosure discussions. Med Health Care and Philos 18, 361–370 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9611-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-014-9611-8

Keywords

Navigation