Advertisement

Continental Philosophy Review

, Volume 44, Issue 4, pp 359–381 | Cite as

Plasticity, motor intentionality and concrete movement in Merleau-Ponty

  • Timothy MooneyEmail author
Article

Abstract

Merleau-Ponty’s explication of concrete or practical movement by way of the Schneider case could be read as ending up close to automatism, neglecting its flexibility and plasticity in the face of obstacles. It can be contended that he already goes off course in his explication of Schneider’s condition. Rasmus Jensen has argued that he assimilates a normal person’s motor intentionality to the patient’s, thereby generating a vacuity problem. I argue that Schneider’s difficulties with certain movements point to a means of broadening Merleau-Ponty’s account of concrete movement, one that he broaches without exploiting. What could do more work is his recognition of a transposition capacity - and hence of a plasticity - in the healthy body’s skill schema. As well as avoiding vacuity, he could forestall the appearance of a dichotomy between practical coping and creativity.

Keywords

Automatism Body schema Concrete Concrete-like Context-familiar Context-strange Creativity Habitual Motor intentionality Movement Plasticity Representation Schneider Transposition capacity Vacuity 

References

  1. Baldwin, Thomas (ed.). 2007. Reading Merleau-Ponty: On phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Benary, W. 1922. Studien zur Untersuchung der Intelligenz bei einem Fall von Seelenblindheit. Psychologische Forschung 2(1): 209–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bergson, Henri. 1971. The creative mind. New York: Philosophical Library. (trans: Andison, M.L.).Google Scholar
  4. Carman, Taylor. 2008. Merleau-Ponty. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  5. Dreyfus, Hubert. 2007. Reply to Romdenh-Romluc. In Baldwin, 59–69.Google Scholar
  6. Glendinning, Simon. 2007. The Genius of Man. In Baldwin, 104–117.Google Scholar
  7. Goldenberg, Georg. 2003. Goldstein and Gelb’s Case Schn.: A Classic Case in Neuropsychology? In Classic cases in neuropsychology, eds. Chris Code et al., vol. 2, 281–299. Hove, Sussex: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
  8. Goldstein, Kurt. 1923. Über die Abhängigkeit der Bewegungen von optischen Vorgängen. Bewegungsstörungen bei Seelenblinden. Monatschrift für Psychiatrie und Neurologie 54 (Festschrift Liepmann), 141–194.Google Scholar
  9. Grünbaum, A.A. 1930. Aphasie und Motorik. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie 130(1): 385–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hass, Lawrence. 2008. Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and time. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (trans, John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson).Google Scholar
  12. Hochheimer, W. 1932. Analyse eines ‘Seelenblinden’ von der Sprache. Psychologische Forschung 16(1): 1–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Husserl, Edmund. 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, Second Book. Dordrecht: Kluwer. (trans, Richard Rojcewicz and André Schuwer).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Jensen, Rasmus T. 2009. Motor intentionality and the case of Schneider. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(3): 371–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Kant, Immanuel. 1933. Immanuel Kant’s critique of pure reason, revised edition. London: Macmillan. (trans, Norman Kemp Smith).Google Scholar
  16. Keat, Russell, et al. 1991. Understanding phenomenology. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  17. Kelly, Sean. 2004. Merleau-Ponty on the body. In The philosophy of the body, ed. M. Proudfoot, 62–76. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1942. La structure du comportement. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
  19. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945. Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Éditions Gallimard.Google Scholar
  20. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962. Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (trans, Colin Smith).Google Scholar
  21. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1963. The structure of behaviour. Boston: Beacon Press. (trans, Alden Fisher).Google Scholar
  22. Milner, A., Goodale David, and A. Melvyn. 1995. The visual brain in action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Mulhall, Stephen. 1996. Heidegger and being and time. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  24. Rietveld, Eric. 2008. The Skillful body as a concernful system of possible actions: Phenomena and neurodynamics. Theory and Psychology 18(3): 341–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Romdenh-Romluc, Komarine. 2007. Merleau-Ponty and the power to Reckon with the possible. In Baldwin, 44–58.Google Scholar
  26. Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1956. Being and nothingness. An essay on phenomenological ontology. New York: Philosophical Library. (trans, Hazel E. Barnes).Google Scholar
  27. Tiermersma, Douwe. 1982. ‘Body-Image’ and ‘Body-Schema’ in the existential phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 13: 246–255.Google Scholar
  28. Zaner, Richard. 1964. The problem of embodiment: Some contributions to a phenomenology of the body. The Hague: Nijhoff.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University College DublinDublinIreland

Personalised recommendations