Abstract
A consequence relation is strongly classical if it has all the theorems and entailments of classical logic as well as the usual meta-rules (such as Conditional Proof). A consequence relation is weakly classical if it has all the theorems and entailments of classical logic but lacks the usual meta-rules. The most familiar example of a weakly classical consequence relation comes from a simple supervaluational approach to modelling vague language. This approach is formally equivalent to an account of logical consequence according to which \(\alpha _1, \ldots , \alpha _n\) entails \(\beta \) just in case \(\Box \alpha _1, \ldots , \Box \alpha _n\) entails \(\Box \beta \) in the modal logic S5. This raises a natural question: If we start with a different underlying modal logic, can we generate a strongly classical logic? This paper explores this question. In particular, it discusses four related technical issues: (1) Which base modal logics generate strongly classical logics and which generate weakly classical logics? (2) Which base logics generate themselves? (3) How can we directly characterize the logic generated from a given base logic? (4) Given a logic that can be generated, which base logics generate it? The answers to these questions have philosophical interest. They can help us to determine whether there is a plausible supervaluational approach to modelling vague language that yields the usual meta-rules. They can also help us to determine the feasibility of other philosophical projects that rely on an analogous formalism, such as the project of defining logical consequence in terms of the preservation of an epistemic status.
Similar content being viewed by others
Availability of data and materials
Not applicable.
References
Avron, A. (1991). Simple consequence relations. Information and Computation, 92, 105–139.
Asher, N., Dever, J., & Pappas, C. (2009). Supervaluations debugged. Mind, 118, 901–933.
Bledin, J. (2014). Logic informed. Mind, 123, 277–316.
Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Chellas, B. Modal Logic: An Introduction (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1980). Reprinted with corrections 1988.
Chellas, B., & Segerberg, K. (1994). Modal logics with the Macintosh rule. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23, 67–86.
Cobreros, P. (2008). Supervaluationism and logical consequence: A third way. Studia Logica, 90, 291–312.
Cobreros, P. (2011). Supervaluationism and classical logic. In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooji, U. Sauerland & H. C. Schmitz (Eds.), Vagueness in communication (pp. 51–63). Berlin: Springer.
Edgington, D. (1993). Wright and Sainsbury on higher-order vagueness. Analysis, 53, 193–200.
Field, H. (2008). Saving Truth from Paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.
Graff Fara, D. (2004). Gap principles, penumbral consequence, and infinitely higher-order vagueness. In J. C. Beall (Ed.), Liars and heaps: New essays on paradox (pp. 195–221). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Heck, R. K. (1993). A note on the logic of (higher-order) vagueness. Analysis, 53, 201–208.
Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 106, 641–660.
Iemhoff, R. (2015). On rules. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44, 697–711.
Jeřábek, E. (2005). Admissible rules of modal logics. Journal of Logic and Computation, 15, 411–31.
Keefe, R. (2000). Supervaluationism and validity. Philosophical Topics, 28, 93–105.
Keefe, R. (2000). Theories of Vagueness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kripke, S. A. (1963). Semantical analysis of modal logic I: Normal propositional calculi. Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 9, 67–96.
Lemmon, E. An Introduction to Modal Logic: The Lemmon Notes (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1977). Written in collaboration with Dana Scott. Edited by Krister Segerberg.
Lorenzen, P. (1955). Einführung in die operative Logik und Mathematik Vol. 78 of Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften (Springer-Verlag, Berlin).
Loś, J., & Suszko, R. (1958). Remarks on sentential logics. Indagationes Mathematicae, 20, 177–183.
Machina, K. (1976). Truth, belief, and vagueness. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5, 47–78.
McGee, V., & McLaughlin, B. (1995). Distinctions without a difference. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 33, 203–251.
McGee, V., & McLaughlin, B. P. (2004). Logical commitment and semantic indeterminacy: A reply to Williamson. Linguistics and Philosophy, 27, 123–136.
Popper, K. (1947). New foundations for logic. Mind, 56, 193–235.
Prawitz, D. (2015). Explaining deductive inference. In H. Wansing (Ed.), Dag Prawitz on proofs and meaning (pp. 65–100). Cham: Springer.
Ripley, D. (2012). Conservatively extending classical logic with transparent truth. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 354–378.
Rybakov, V. V. (1997). Admissibility of Logical Inference Rules Vol. 136 of Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics (Elsevier, Amsterdam).
Sahlqvist, H. (1975). Completeness and correspondence in the first and second order semantics for modal logic. In S. Kanger (Ed.), Proceedings of the third scandinavian logic symposium (Vol. 82 of Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pp. 110–143). Elsevier.
Schechter, J. (forthcoming). Epistemic characterizations of validity and level-bridging principles. Philosophical Studies.
Schechter, J. (2011). Juxtaposition: A new way to combine logics. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4, 560–606.
Shapiro, S. (2006). Vagueness in Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Smiley, T. (1963). Relative necessity. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 28, 113–134.
Sundholm, G. (2012). “Inference versus consequence" revisited: Inference, consequence, conditional, implication. Synthese, 187, 943–956.
Sundholm, G. (1983). Systems of deduction. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 1, pp. 133–188). Dordrecht: Reidel.
Varzi, A. (2007). Supervaluationism and its logics. Mind, 116, 633–676.
Williams, J. R. (2008). Supervaluationism and logical revisionism. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 192–212.
Williamson, T. (1988). Assertion, denial and some cancellation rules in modal logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 299–318.
Williamson, T. (1992). An alternative rule of disjunction in modal logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 33, 89–100.
Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. New York: Routledge.
Williamson, T. (1996). Some admissible rules in modal systems with the Brouwerian axiom. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 4, 283–303.
Williamson, T. (2018). Supervaluationism and good reasoning. Theoria, 33, 521–537.
Wright, C. (1992). Is higher order vagueness coherent? Analysis, 52, 129–139.
Acknowledgements
Thanks to Riki Heck, Stephan Krämer, Stephan Leuenberger, and Bruno Whittle for discussion. Thanks to two anonymous referees for extensive and helpful comments.
Funding
No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
Not applicable.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Ethical Approval
Not applicable.
Competing interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Schechter, J. Supervaluationism, Modal Logic, and Weakly Classical Logic. J Philos Logic 53, 411–461 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-023-09737-0
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-023-09737-0