Skip to main content
Log in

Indicative Conditionals and Graded Information

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I propose an account of indicative conditionals that combines features of minimal change semantics and information semantics. As in information semantics, conditionals are interpreted relative to an information state in accordance with the Ramsey test idea: “if p then q” is supported at a state s iff q is supported at the hypothetical state s[p] obtained by restricting s to the p-worlds. However, information states are not modeled as simple sets of worlds, but by means of a Lewisian system of spheres. Worlds in the inner sphere are considered possible; worlds outside of it are ruled out, but to different degrees. In this way, even when a state supports “not p”, it is still possible to suppose p consistently. I argue that this account does better than its predecessors with respect to a set of desiderata concerning inferences with conditionals. In particular, it captures three important facts: (i) that a conditional is logically independent from its antecedent; (ii) that a sequence of antecedents behaves like a single conjunctive antecedent (the import-export equivalence); and (iii) that conditionals restrict the quantification domain of epistemic modals. I also discuss two ways to construe the role of a premise, and propose a generalized notion of entailment that keeps the two apart.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Adams, E. (1965). The logic of conditionals. Inquiry, 8(1-4), 166–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Adams, E. (1970). Subjunctive and indicative conditionals. Foundations of Language, 6(1), 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Adams, E. (1975). The logic of conditionals: an application of probability to deductive logic Vol. 86. Berlin: Springer Science & Business Media.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. Alchourrón, C., Gärdenfors, P., Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50(02), 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Alonso-Ovalle, L. (2009). Counterfactuals, correlatives, and disjunction. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32, 207–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Arló-Costa, H. (1997). Belief revision conditionals: models of suppositional reasoning. Technical Report, Carnegie Mellon University.

  7. Arló-Costa, H., & Levi, I. (1996). Two notions of epistemic validity. Synthese, 109(2), 217–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2006). Dynamic belief revision over multi-agent plausibility models. In Proceedings of LOFT.

  9. Bledin, J. (2014). Logic informed. Mind, 123(490), 277–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Bledin, J. (2015). Modus ponens defended. The Journal of Philosophy, 112 (2), 57–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Bledin, J. (2018). Fatalism and the logic of unconditionals. Noûs.

  12. Bledin, J., & Lando, T. (2018). Closure and epistemic modals. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 97(1), 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Board, O. (2004). Dynamic interactive epistemology. Games and Economic Behavior, 49(1), 49–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Briggs, R. (2012). Interventionist counterfactuals. Philosophical Studies, 160 (1), 139–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Cantwell, J. (2008). Changing the modal context. Theoria, 74(4), 331–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Ciardelli, I. (2016). Lifting conditionals to inquisitive semantics. In M. Moroney, C.-R. Little, J. Collard, D. Burgdorf (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) 26. Ithaca: LSA and CLC Publications.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Dekker, P. (1993). Transsentential meditations. Ups and downs in dynamic semantics. Ph.D thesis, ILLC, University of Amsterdam.

  18. Edgington, D. (1986). Do conditionals have truth conditions? Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, 18(52), 3–39.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Edgington, D. (1995). On conditionals. Mind, 104, 235–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Egré, P., & Politzer, G. (2013). On the negation of indicative conditionals. In M. Aloni, M. Franke, F. Roelofsen (Eds.), Proceedings of the nineteenth Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 10–18).

  21. Fine, K. (2017). Truthmaker semantics. In B. Hale, C. Wright, A. Miller (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 556–577). Wiley.

  22. Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux: Modeling the dynamics of the epistemic states. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Gibbard, A. (1980). Two recent theories of conditionals. In Ifs: Conditionals, beliefs, decision, chance, time (pp. 211–247). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  24. Gillies, A. (2004). Epistemic conditionals and conditional epistemics. Noûs, 38(4), 585–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Gillies, A. (2009). On truth-conditions for if (but not quite only if ). Philosophical Review, 118(3), 325–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Gillies, A.S. (2007). Counterfactual scorekeeping. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(3), 329–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Gillies, A.S. (2010). Iffiness. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3, 4–1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Gillies, A.S. (2018). Updating data semantics. Mind.

  29. Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Herzberger, H.G. (1979). Counterfactuals and consistency. The Journal of Philosophy, 76(2), 83–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Higginbotham, J. (1986). Linguistic theory and Davidson’s program in semantics. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation: perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 29–48). Basil Blackwell.

  32. Khoo, J. (2018). Disjunctive antecedent conditionals. Synthese.

  33. Klinedinst, N. (2010). Quantified conditionals and conditional excluded middle. Journal of Semantics, 28(1), 149–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). Ifs and oughts. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(3), 115–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Kratzer, A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In H. Eikmeyer, & H. Rieser (Eds.), Words, worlds, and contexts: new approaches in word semantics (pp. 38–74). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

  36. Kratzer, A. (1986). Conditionals. Chicago Linguistics Society, 22(2), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Kraus, S., Lehmann, D., Magidor, M. (1990). Nonmonotonic reasoning, preferential models and cumulative logics. Artificial Intelligence, 44(1-2), 167–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Leitgeb, H. (2010). On the Ramsey test without triviality. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(1), 21–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Levi, I. (1988). Iteration of conditionals and the Ramsey test. Synthese, 76(1), 49–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Basil Blackwell.

  41. McGee, V. (1985). A counterexample to modus ponens. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(9), 462–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: models, reasoning and inference Vol. 29. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Price, H. (1983). Does “probably” modify sense? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 396–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Ramsey, F.P. (1929). General propositions and causality. In D. H. Mellor (Ed.), F.P. Ramsey: philosophical papers. Cambridge University Press.

  45. Rott, H. (1989). Conditionals and theory change: revisions, expansions, and additions. Synthese, 81(1), 91–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Santorio, P. (2017). Conditional excluded middle in informational semantics. In T. V. G. Alexandre Cremers, & F. Roelofsen (Eds.), Proceedings of the 21st Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 385–394).

  47. Santorio, P. (2018). Alternatives and truthmakers in conditional semantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 115(10), 513–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Schulz, K. (2011). If you’d wiggled a, then b would’ve changed. Synthese, 179 (2), 239–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Schulz, M. (2010). Epistemic modals and informational consequence. Synthese, 174(3), 385–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Schulz, M. (2018). Modus ponens under the restrictor view. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47(6), 1001–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Segerberg, K. (1998). Irrevocable belief revision in dynamic doxastic logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 39(3), 287–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in Logical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  53. Stalnaker, R. (1976). Indicative conditionals. In Ifs (pp. 193–210). Reidel.

  54. Starr, W. (2014). A uniform theory of conditionals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(6), 1019–1064.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Veltman, F. (1981). Data semantics. In J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, M. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal Methods in the Study of Language. Mathematical Centre.

  56. Veltman, F. (1985). Logics for conditionals. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam.

  57. Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25(3), 221–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. von Fintel, K. (1997). Bare plurals, bare conditionals, and only. Journal of Semantics, 14(1), 1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. von Fintel, K. (1998). The presupposition of subjunctive conditionals. The Interpretive Tract, 25, 29–44.

    Google Scholar 

  60. von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. (2010). Might made right. In A. Egan, & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  61. Willer, M. (2014). Dynamic thoughts on ifs and oughts. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14(28), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Willer, M. (2017). Lessons from Sobel sequences. Semantics and Pragmatics, 10, Article 4.

  63. Willer, M. (2018). Simplifying with free choice. Topoi, 37(3), 379–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116(464), 983–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Yalcin, S. (2011). Nonfactualism about epistemic modality. In A. Egan, & B. Weatherson (Eds.), Epistemic Modality. Oxford University Press.

  66. Yalcin, S. (2012). A counterexample to modus tollens. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(6), 1001–1024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Yalcin, S. (2015). Epistemic modality de re. Ergo, 19(2), 475–527.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For inspiring discussions and/or useful feedback on earlier drafts, I am grateful to Maria Aloni, Justin Bledin, Bruno Jacinto, Hannes Leitgeb, Vít Punčochár, Floris Roelofsen, Lorenzo Rossi, Katrin Schulz, Frank Veltman, Malte Willer, Seth Yalcin, and two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ivano Ciardelli.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ciardelli, I. Indicative Conditionals and Graded Information. J Philos Logic 49, 509–549 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-019-09528-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-019-09528-6

Keywords

Navigation