Journal of Philosophical Logic

, Volume 44, Issue 6, pp 741–753 | Cite as

On the use (and abuse) of Logic in Game Theory

Article
  • 378 Downloads

Keywords

Logic and games Epistemic game theory Epistemic logic 

References

  1. 1.
    Abramsky, S. (2007). A compositional game semantics for multi-agent logics of partial information. Volume 1 of Texts in Logic and Games, pp. 11–48. Amsterdam University Press.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Apt, K., & Zvesper, J. (2010). Public announcements in strategic games with arbitrary strategy sets In Proceedings of LOFT 2010.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Arrow, K. (1951). Mathematical models in the social sciences. In Lerner, D. and Lasswell, H. (Eds.) The Policy Sciences. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Asheim, G., & Dufwenberg, M. (2003). Admissibility and common belief. Game and Economic Behavior, 42, 208–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Aumann, R. (1985). What is game theory trying to accomplish? In Arrow, K. and Honkapohja, S. (Eds.), Frontiers of Economics Oxford.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Aumann, R., & Brandenburger, A. (1995). Epistemic conditions for Nash equilibrium. Econometrica, 63, 1161–1180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Bacharach, M. (1993). Variable universe games, In BInmore, K. Kirman, A. and Tami, P. (Eds.), Frontiers of Game Theory, The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Bacharach, M. (2006). Beyond Individual Choices Teams and Frames in Game Theory. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Bacharach, M.O.L. (1997). The epistemic structure of a theory of a game. In Bacharach, M. Gerard-Varet, L. Mongin, P. and Shin, H. (Eds.), em Epistemic Logic and the Theory of Games and Decisions, Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Baltag, A., Smets, S., & Zvesper, J. (2009). Keep ‘hoping’ for rationality: a solution to the backwards induction paradox. Synthese, 169, 301–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Bardsley, N., Mehta, J., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (2010). The nature of salience revisited: Cognitve hierarchy theory versus team reasoning. Economic Journal, 120(543), 40–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    Bicchieri, C. (1993). Rationality and Coordination. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Binmore, K. (1987). Modeling rational players: Part I. Economics and Philosophy, 3, 179–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Binmore, K. (2009). Rational Decisions. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Bonanno, G., & Battigalli, P. (1999). Recent results on belief, knowledge and the epistemic foundations of game theory. Research in Economics, 53(2), 149–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Bonanno, G., & Dégremont, C. (2014). Logic and game theory. In Trends in Logic: Papers on the work of Johan van Benthem, Volume Forthcoming. Springer.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Brandenburger, A. (2007). The power of paradox: some recent developments in interactive epistemology. International Journal of Game Theory, 35, 465–492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Bratman, M. (2007). Structures of Agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Cubitt, R., & Sugden, R. (1994). Rationally justifiable play and the theory of non-cooperative games. The Economic Journal, 104, 798–803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Cubitt, R., & Sugden, R. (2011). Common reasoning in games A Lewisian analysis of common knowledge of rationality. CeDEx Discussion Paper.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Cubitt, R.P., & Sugden, R. (175). Common Knowledge, Salience and Convention: A Reconstruction of David Lewis’ Game Theory. Economics and Philosophy, 19(2).Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Fitting, M. (2011). Reasoning about games. Studia Logica, 99(1-3), 143–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Geanakoplos, J., Pearce, D., & Stacchetti, E. (1999). Psychological games and sequential rationality. Games and Economic Behavior, 1(1), 60–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Ghosh, S., & Ramanujam, R. (2011). Strategies in games: A logic-automata study. In Lectures on Logic and Computation, Volume LNCS 7388.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Goranko, V., & Jamroga, W. (2004). Comparing semantics of logics for multi-agent systems. Synthese: Knowledge. Rationality, and Action, 139(2), 241–280.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Grädel, E. (2011). Back and Forth Between Logics and Games. In Lectures in Game Theory for Computer Scientists, Springer.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Halpern, J. (1999). Set-theoretic completeness for epistemic and conditional logic. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 26, 1–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Halpern, J., Bjorndahl, A., & Pass, R. (2013). Language-based games. In Proceedings of the Fourteenth Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge, ACM Press.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Harman, G. (1999). Reasoning Meaning and Mind Chapter Rationality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Harsanyi, J. (1975). The tracing procedure: A bayesian approach to defining a solution for n-person noncooperative games. International Journal of Game Theory, 4, 61–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Hodges, W. (2013). Logic and games, In Zalta, E.N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 ed.)Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Hu, H., & Stuart, H.W. (2001). An epistemic analysis of the harsanyi transformation. International Journal of Game Theory, 30, 517–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. 33.
    Huber, F. (2013). Formal representations of belief. In Zalta, E.N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 ed.)Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Kreps, D. (1990). Game Theory and Economic Modelling. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Lorini, E., & Schwarzentruber, F. (2010). A modal logic of epistemic games. Games, 1(4), 478–526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    McClennen, E (1990). Rationality and Dynamic Choice Foundational Explorations. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    Pacuit, E. (2013a). Dynamic epistemic logic I: Modeling knowledge and belief. Philosophy Compass, 8(9), 798–814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. 38.
    Pacuit, E. (2013b). Dynamic epistemic logic II: Logics of information change. Philosophy Compass, 8(9), 815–833.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. 39.
    Pacuit, E. (2014). Strategic reasoning in games. Manuscript.Google Scholar
  40. 40.
    Pacuit, E., & Roy, O. (2015). Epistemic game theory. In Zalta, E.N. (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Parikh, R. (1983). Propositional game logic In Proceedings of FOCS.Google Scholar
  42. 42.
    Parikh, R. (2002). Social software. Synthese, 132(3).Google Scholar
  43. 43.
    Rabinowicz, W. (1992). Tortous labyrinth: Noncooperative normal-form games between hyperrational players, In Bicchieri, C. Chiara, M.L.D. (Eds.), Knowledge, Belief and Strategic Interaction.Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    Ramanujam, R., & Simon, S.E. (2008). Dynamic logic on games with structured strategies In Proceedings of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning.Google Scholar
  45. 45.
    Schelling, T. (1960). The Strategy of Conflict. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  46. 46.
    Skyrms, B. (1990). The Dynamics of Rational Deliberation. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  47. 47.
    Stalnaker, R. (1999). Extensive and strategic forms: Games and models for games. Research in Economics, 53, 293–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. 48.
    Sugden, R. (2003). The logic of team reasoning. Philosophical Explorations, 63, 165–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. 49.
    van Benthem, J. (1996). Exploring Logical Dynamics. CSLI Press.Google Scholar
  50. 50.
    van Benthem, J. (2005). Where is logic going and should it. Topoi, 25, 117–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. 51.
    van Benthem, J (2007). Rational dynamics and epistemic logic in games. International Game Theory Review, 9(1), 13–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. 52.
    van Benthem, J. (2008). Logic and reasong: do the facts matter. Studia Logica, 88(1), 67–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. 53.
    van Benthem, J. (2011). Logical Dynamics of Information and Interaction. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  54. 54.
    van Benthem, J. (2014). Logic in Games. The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  55. 55.
    van Benthem, J., & Gheerbrant, A. (2010). Game solution, epistemic dynamics and fixed-point logics. Fund. Inform, 100, 1–23.Google Scholar
  56. 56.
    van Benthem, J., Pacuit, E., & Roy, O. (2011). Towards a theory of play: A logical perspective on games and interaction. Games, 2(1), 52–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. 57.
    van der Hoek, W., & Pauly, M. (2006). Modal logic for games and information. In Blackburn, P. van Benthem, J. and Wolter, F. (Eds.), em Handbook of Modal Logic, Volume 3 of Studies in Logic, Elsevier.Google Scholar
  58. 58.
    van der Hoek, W., & Wooldridge, M. (2003). Towards a logic of rational agency. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 11(2), 135–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. 59.
    van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (2007). Dynamic Epistemic Logic. Synthese Library. Springer.Google Scholar
  60. 60.
    van Eijck, J., & Vergrugge, R. (Eds.) (2009). Discourses on Social Software. Texts in Logic and Games.Google Scholar
  61. 61.
    Vestergaard, R. (2006). A constructive approach to sequential Nash equilibria. Information Processes Letter, 97(2), 46–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. 62.
    Wooldridge, M. (2000). Reasoning about Rational Agents. The MIT Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of MarylandCollege ParkUSA

Personalised recommendations