Advertisement

Journal of Philosophical Logic

, Volume 43, Issue 2–3, pp 471–498 | Cite as

A Closer Look at Manifest Consequence

  • Max Weiss
Article

Abstract

Fine (2007) argues that Frege’s puzzle and its relatives demonstrate a need for a basic reorientation of the field of semantics. According to this reorientation, the domain of semantic facts would be closed not under the classical consequence relation but only under a stronger relation Fine calls “manifest consequence.” I examine Fine’s informally sketched analyses of manifest consequence, showing that each can be amended to determine a class of strong consequence relations. A best candidate relation emerges from each of the two classes, and I prove that the two candidates extensionally coincide. The resulting consequence relation is of independent interest, for it might be held to constitute a cogent standard of reasoning that proceeds under a deficient grasp on the identity of objects.

Keywords

Kit fine Manifest consequence Russellian propositions Singular propositions Identity Distinctness Direct reference Semantic fact Frege Semantics Logic 

References

  1. 1.
    Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Fine, K. (2007). Semantic relationism. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Reprinted in McGuinness, B. (Ed.) (1984). Gottlob Frege: collected papers on mathematics, logic and philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Frege, G. (1883). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Translated in Austin, J.L. (1950). The foundations of arithmetic. London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Goldfarb, W. (2001). Frege’s conception of logic. In Floyd, J., & Shieh, S. (2001). Future pasts. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Kaplan, D. (1986). Opacity. In Hahn, L.E., & Schilpp, P.A. (Eds.) (1998). The philosophy of W.V. Quine. LaSalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In Almog, J., Perry, J., Wettstein, H. (Eds.) (1998). Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). New York: Oxford.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Kaplan, D. (1990). Words. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 64, 93–119.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Krivine, J.L. (2007). Theorie des Ensembles. Paris: Cassini.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22(1–2), 18–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    McGuiness, B. (Ed.), & Kaal, H. (Trans.). Gottlob Frege: philosophical and mathematical correspondence. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Montague, R. (1960). On the nature of certain philosophical entities. The Monist, 53, 159–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. 13.
    Moore, G.E. (1899). The nature of judgment. Mind, New Series, 8(30), 176–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Potter, M., & Ricketts, T. (Eds.) (2011). The Cambridge companion to Frege. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Russell, B.A.E. (1903). The principles of mathematics. London: Norton.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Soames, S. (1987). Direct reference, propositional attitudes, and semantic content. Philosophical Topics, 15, 47–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    Tarski, A. (1933). The concept of truth in formalized languages. Translated in Corcoran, J. (Ed.) (1983). Logic, semantics, metamathematics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    United States Department of Justice (2011). Crime data brief: identity theft reported by households, 2005–2010. http://bjs.ojp.usdoj.gov/content/pub/pdf/itrh0510.pdf. Accessed 2 Jan 2013.
  19. 19.
    Wettstein, H.K. (1986). Has semantics rested on a mistake? The Journal of Philosophy, 83(4), 185–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of British ColumbiaVancouverCanada

Personalised recommendations