Advertisement

Linguistics and Philosophy

, Volume 41, Issue 6, pp 623–664 | Cite as

The semantic roots of positive polarity: epistemic modal verbs and adverbs in English, Greek and Italian

  • Anastasia Giannakidou
  • Alda Mari
Article

Abstract

Epistemic modal verbs and adverbs of necessity are claimed to be positive polarity items. We study their behavior by examining modal spread, a phenomenon that appears redundant or even anomalous, since it involves two apparent modal operators being interpreted as a single modality. We propose an analysis in which the modal adverb is an argument of the MUST modal, providing a meta-evaluation \(\mathcal {O}\) which ranks the Ideal, stereotypical worlds in the modal base as better possibilities than the Non-Ideal worlds in it. MUST and possibility modals differ in that the latter have an empty \(\mathcal {O}\), a default that can be negotiated. Languages vary in the malleability of this parameter. Positive polarity is derived as a conflict between the ranking imposed by \(\mathcal {O}\)—which requires that the Ideal worlds be better possibilities than Non-Ideal worlds—and the effect of higher negation which renders the Ideal set non-homogenous. Applying the ordering over such a non-homogeneous set would express preference towards both p and \(\lnot p \) worlds thus rendering the sentence uninformative. Negative polarity MUST and possibility modals, on the other hand, contain an empty \(\mathcal {O}\), application of higher negation therefore poses no problem. This account is the first to connect modal spread to positive polarity of necessity modals, and captures the properties of both in a unified analysis.

Keywords

Positive polarity Modal spread Epistemic modality Epistemic adverbs Ordering semantics 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

Acknowledgements

No work is done in isolation, and we want to thank the many colleagues that became familiar with our work and offered us comments when we presented material related to this paper, as early as the ‘Futur dans les langues Romanes’ workshop held in Neuchâtel in 2012, the Amsterdam Colloquium in 2013, and the Linguistics and Philosophy seminar in Chicago in 2014. The specific shape of the material discussed in this paper owes a lot to the insights and advice we received from our editor Paul Portner, who went beyond the call of duty to encourage us to develop our arguments to their fullest. We are thankful for his help. Many thanks also to Jason Merchant and Hedde Zeijlstra for their suggestions on the more syntactic aspects of the paper, to Mingya Liu, Claire Beyssade and Lavi Wolf for their comments on epistemic commitment and to the anonymous reviewers of Linguistics and Philosophy for their careful reading of the paper, and for offering generously their suggestions and insights. Alda Mari gratefully thanks the ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC and ANR- 10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL.

References

  1. Anand, P., & Brasoveanu, A. (2010). Modal concord as modal modification. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung (Vol. 14, pp. 19–36).Google Scholar
  2. Asher, N., & Morreau, M. (1995). What some generic sentences mean. In G. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book. Chicago: CUP.Google Scholar
  3. Beaver, D., & Frazee, J. (2016). Semantics. In The handbook of computational linguistics. Online Publication.  https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199573691.013.29.
  4. Bertinetto, P. M. (1979). Alcune ipotesi sul nostro futuro (con alcune osservazioni su potere e dovere). Rivista di grammatica generativa, 4, 77–138.Google Scholar
  5. Bonami, O., & Godard, G. (2008). Lexical semantics and pragmatics of evaluative adverbs. In L. McNally & C. Kennedy (Eds.), Adverbs and adjectives: Syntax, semantics and discourse (pp. 274–304). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Condoravdi, C. (2002). Temporal interpretation of modals: Modals for the present and for the past. In D. Beaver, L. D. Cassillas Maritinez, B. Z. Clark, & S. Kaufmann (Eds.), The construction of meaning. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar
  7. Cui, Y. (2015). Modals in the scope of attitudes: A corpus study of attitude-modal combinations in Mandarin Chinese. Ph.D. thesis, Georgetown University.Google Scholar
  8. de Marneffe, M., Manning, C., & Potts, C. (2012). Did it happen? The pragmatic complexity of the veridicality judgement. Computational Linguistics, 38, 300–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dowty, D. (1979). Word meaning and Montague grammar. Dordrech: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Ernst, T. (2009). Speaker oriented adverbs. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 27, 497–544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Farkas, D. F. (1985). Intensional descriptions and the romance subjunctive. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
  12. Farkas, D. F. (1992). On the semantics of subjunctive complements. In P. Hirschbühler et al. (Eds.), Romance languages and modern linguistic theory (pp. 69–104). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Geurts, B., & Huitink, J. (2006). Modal concord. In P. Dekker & H. Zeijlstra (Eds.), Concord and the syntax–semantics interface (pp. 15–20). Malaga: ESSLLI.Google Scholar
  14. Giannakidou, A. (1994). The semantic licensing of NPIs and the Modern Greek subjunctive. In A. de Boer, H. de Hoop, & H. de Swart (Eds.), Language and cognition. Yearbook of the Research Group for Theoretical and Experimental Linguistics (Vol. 4, pp. 55–68). Groningen: University of Groningen.Google Scholar
  15. Giannakidou, A. (1997). The landscape of polarity items. Ph.D. thesis, University of Groningen, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  16. Giannakidou, A. (1998). Polarity sensitivity as (non)veridical dependency. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Giannakidou, A. (1999). Affective dependencies. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22, 367–421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Giannakidou, A. (2009). The dependency of the subjunctive revisited: Temporal semantics and polarity. Lingua, 120, 1883–1908.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Giannakidou, A. (2011). Positive polarity items and negative polarity items: Variation, licensing, and compositionality. In C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (2nd ed.). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  20. Giannakidou, A. (2012). The Greek future as an epistemic modal. In Proceedings of ICGL 10.Google Scholar
  21. Giannakidou, A. (2013). Inquisitive assertions and nonveridicality. In M. Aloni, M. Franke, & F. Roelofsen (Eds.), The dynamic, inquisitive, and visionary life of \(\phi \), \(?\phi \) and possibly \(\phi \) , a feestschrift for Jeroen Groenendijk, Martin Stokhof and Frank Veltman (pp. 115–126). Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  22. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2012a). Italian and Greek futures as epistemic operators. Proceedings of CLS, 48, 247–262.Google Scholar
  23. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2012b). The future of Greek and Italian: An epistemic analysis. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung (Vol. 17, pp. 255–2700). http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/Dk3NGEwY/GiannakidouMari.pdf.
  24. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2013). A two dimensional analysis of the future: Modal adverbs and speaker’s bias. Proceedings of the Amsterdam Colloquium, 2013, 115–122.Google Scholar
  25. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2016a). Emotive predicates and the subjunctive: A flexible mood OT account based on (non)veridicality. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung (Vol. 20, pp. 288–305).Google Scholar
  26. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2016b). Tense, mood, and modality: New perspectives on old questions. Epistemic future and epistemic MUST: Nonveridicality, evidence, and partial knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  27. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2017). La dimension épistemique du futur: le rôle des adverbes. In L. Baranzini & L. de Saussure (Eds.), Le Futur dans les langues Romanes. Bern: Peter Lang AG.Google Scholar
  28. Giannakidou, A., & Mari, A. (2018). A unified analysis of the future as epistemic modality: The view from Greek and Italian. Natural Language and Linguistic theory, 36, 85–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Giorgi, A., & Pianesi, F. (1997). Tense and aspect: Form semantics to morphosyntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Grosz, P. (2010). Grading modality: A new approach to modal concord and its relatives. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung (Vol. 14, pp. 185–201). http://www.univie.ac.at/sub14/.
  31. Grosz, P. (2012). On the grammar of optative constructions. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  32. Hacquard, V. (2006). Aspects of modality. PhD thesis, MIT.Google Scholar
  33. Hacquard, V. (2010). On the event relativity of modal auxiliaries. Natural Language Semantics, 18(1), 79–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Hacquard, V., & Wellwood, A. (2012). Embedding epistemic modals in English: A corpus-based study. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5(4), 1–29.Google Scholar
  35. Harris, J. A., & Potts, C. (2009). Perspective-shifting with appositives and expressives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 32(6), 523–552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief. Cornell: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Homer, V. (2015). Neg-raising and positive polarity: The view from modals. Semantics & Pragmatics, 8, 1–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Horn, L. (2001). A natural history of negation. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  39. Huitink, J. (2012). Modal concord. A case study in Dutch. Journal of Semantics, 29(3), 403–437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Huitink, J. (2014). Modal concord. In L. Matthewson, C. Meier, H. Rullman, & T. E. Zimmermann (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to semantics. Oxford: Wiley.Google Scholar
  41. Iatridou, S., & Zeijlstra, H. (2013). Negation, polarity and deontic modals. Linguistic Inquiry, 44, 529–568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Israel, M. (1996). Polarity sensitivity as lexical semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 19(6), 619–666.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Karttunen, L. (1972). Possible and must. In J. Kimball (Ed.), Syntax and Semantics (Vol. 1, pp. 1–20). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  44. Knobe, J., & Szabo, G. S. (2013). Modals with a taste of the deontic. Semantics and Pragmatics, 6, 1–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Kratzer, A. (1991). Modality. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 639–650). Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  46. Krifka, M. (2015). Bias in commitment space semantics: Declarative questions, negated questions, and question tags. In: Proceedings of SALT (Vol. 25, pp. 328–345).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Landman, F. (1992). The progressive. Natural language semantics, 1(1), 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Lasersohn, P. (2005). Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28, 643–686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Lassiter, D. (2016). Must, knowledge, and (in)directness. Natural Language Semantics, 24, 117–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Lauer, S. (2013). Towards a dynamic pragmatics. Ph.D. thesis, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  51. Liu, M. (2009). Speaker-oriented adverbs of the German-wise sort. In Proceedings of Sinn ind Bedeutung (pp. 333–346).Google Scholar
  52. Liu, M. (2012). Multidimensional semantics for evaluative adverbs. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  53. Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Mari, A. (2003). Principes d’identification et de catégorisation du sens: le cas de ‘avec’ ou l’association par les canaux. Paris: L’Harmattan.Google Scholar
  55. Mari, A. (2005). Intensional and epistemic wholes. In E. Machery, M. Werning, & G. Schurz (Eds.), The compositionality of meaning and content. Vol I: Foundational issues. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
  56. Mari, A. (2009a). Disambiguating the Italian future. In Proceedings of generative lexicon (pp. 209–216).Google Scholar
  57. Mari, A. (2009b). Future, judges and normalcy conditions. Selected talk at Chronos 10, Austin, Texas. https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/ijn_00354462/.
  58. Mari, A. (2014). Each other, asymmetry and reasonable futures. Journal of Semantics, 31(2), 209–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Mari, A. (2015a). Modalités et Temps. Bern: Peter Lang AG.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Mari, A. (2015b). French future: Exploring the future ratification hypothesis. Journal of French Language Studies.  https://doi.org/10.1017/S0959269515000289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Mari, A. (2015c). Overt and covert modality in generic sentences. Cahiers Chronos, 27, 265–288.Google Scholar
  62. Mari, A. (2016). Assertability conditions of epistemic (and fictional) attitudes and mood variation. Proceedings of SALT, 26, 61–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Mari, A. (2017). Actuality entailments: When the modality is in the presupposition. Lecture Notes in Computer Science (pp. 191–210). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Mari, A. (2018). Believing and asserting. Evidence from mood shift. Workshop InqBnB2, Amsterdam, December 18–20, 2018. http://jakubdotlacil.com/inqbnb2/alda.pdf.
  65. Mari, A., Beyssade, C., & Del Prete, F. (2012). Introduction. In A. Mari, C. Beyssade, & F. Del Prete (Eds.), Genericity (pp. 1–92). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Matthewson, L., Rullmann, H., & Davis, H. (2007). Evidentials as epistemic modals: Evidence from St’at’imcets. The Linguistic Variation Yearbook, 7, 201–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Mayol, L., & Castroviejo, E. (2013). (Non)integrated evaluative adverbs in questions: A cross-Romance study. Language, 89(2), 195–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Moss, S. (2015). On the semantics and pragmatics of epistemic vocabulary. Semantics and Pragmatics, 8, 1–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Narrog, H. (2012). Modality, subjectivity, and semantic change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Nilsen, Ø. (2004). Domains for adverbs. Lingua, 114(6), 809–847.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Portner, P. (1998). The progressive in modal semantics. Language, 74(4), 760–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Portner, P. (2009). Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  73. Portner, P., & Rubinstein, A. (2016). Extreme and non-extreme deontic modals. In N. Charlow & M. Chrisman (Eds.), Deontic modality. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  74. Potts, C. (2007). The expressive dimension. Theoretical Linguistics, 33(2), 165–197.Google Scholar
  75. Progovac, L. (1994). Positive and negative polarity: A binding approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Rizzi, L. (1997). The fine structure of the left periphery. In L. Haegeman (Ed.), Elements of grammar: A handbook of generative syntax (pp. 281–337). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Rubinstein, A. (2014). On necessity and comparison. Pacific Philosophical Quaterly, 95, 512–554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Smirnova, A. (2013). Evidentiality in Bulgarian. Journal of Semantics, 30, 479–532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Staraki, E. (2013). Greek modality. Chicago: University of Chicago dissertation.Google Scholar
  80. Stephenson, T. (2007). Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(4), 487–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Szabolcsi, A. (2004). Positive polarity—Negative polarity. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 22, 409–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. van der Wouden, T. (1994). Negative contexts. Ph.D. thesis, University of Groningen.Google Scholar
  83. von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. (2010). Must...stay... strong !. Natural Language Semantics, 18, 351–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2008a). Time and modality. In J. Guéron & J. Lacarme (Eds.), How to say ought in foreign: The composition of weak necessity modals (pp. 115–141). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  85. von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2008b). How to say ought in foreign: The composition of weak necessity modals. In J. Guéron & J. Lacarme (Eds.), Time and modality (pp. 115–141). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Willer, M. (2013). Dynamics of epistemic modality. Philosophical Review, 122, 45–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Willett, T. (1988). A cross-linguistic survey of the grammaticalization of evidentiality. Studies in Language, 12, 51–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Wolf, L. (2013). Degrees of assertion. Ph.D. dissertation, Ben Gurion University.Google Scholar
  89. Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116, 983–1026.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Zanuttini, R. (1992). Negation and clausal structure: A comparative study of romance languages. Ph.D. thesis, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
  91. Zeijlstra, E. (2017). Universal quantifiers PPIs. Glossa, 2, 91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Linguistics DepartmentUniversity of ChicagoChicagoUSA
  2. 2.CNRS, ENS, EHESS, PSLInstitut Jean NicodParisFrance

Personalised recommendations