Discourse and logical form: pronouns, attention and coherence
- 480 Downloads
- 6 Citations
Abstract
Traditionally, pronouns are treated as ambiguous between bound and demonstrative uses. Bound uses are non-referential and function as bound variables, and demonstrative uses are referential and take as a semantic value their referent, an object picked out jointly by linguistic meaning and a further cue—an accompanying demonstration, an appropriate and adequately transparent speaker’s intention, or both. In this paper, we challenge tradition and argue that both demonstrative and bound pronouns are dependent on, and co-vary with, antecedent expressions. Moreover, the semantic value of a pronoun is never determined, even partly, by extra-linguistic cues; it is fixed, invariably and unambiguously, by features of its context of use governed entirely by linguistic rules. We exploit the mechanisms of Centering and Coherence theories to develop a precise and general meta-semantics for pronouns, according to which the semantic value of a pronoun is determined by what is at the center of attention in a coherent discourse. Since the notions of attention and coherence are, we argue, governed by linguistic rules, we can give a uniform analysis of pronoun resolution that covers bound, demonstrative, and even discourse bound (“E-type”) readings. Just as the semantic value of the first-person pronoun ‘I’ is conventionally set by a particular feature of its context of use—namely, the speaker—so too, we will argue, the semantic values of other pronouns, including ‘he’, are conventionally set by particular features of the context of use.
Keywords
Pronouns Logical form Intentionalism Convention Attention Coherence DiscoursePreview
Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.
References
- Alahverdzhieva, K., & Lascarides, A. (2011). An HPSG approach to synchronous deixis and speech. In S. Muller (Ed.), Proceedings of the 18th international conference on head-driven phase structure grammar (HPSG) (pp. 6–24). Seattle: USA.Google Scholar
- Asher, N., & Lascarides, A. (2003). Logics of conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Bittner, M. (2007). Aspectual universals of temporal anaphora. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), Theoretical and Crosslinguistic Approaches to the Semantics of Aspect. Chap. 11, pp 349–385. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
- Bittner, M. (2014). Temporality: Universals and variation. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
- Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding: The Pisa lectures. Holland: Foris Publications (Reprint: 7th Edition. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter, 1993).Google Scholar
- Cohen, S. (1998). Contextualist solutions to epistemological problems: Scepticism, Gettier, and the Lottery. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76, 289–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Dekker, P. (2011). Dynamic semantics. In K. von Heusinger, C. Maienborn, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 1, pp. 923–945). Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter.Google Scholar
- Dowell, J. L. (2011). Flexible Contextualist Account of Epistmeic Modals. Philosopers’ Imprint, 11, 1–25.Google Scholar
- Elbourne, P. (2008). Implicit content and the argument from binding. Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory XVIII (SALT 18) (pp. 284–301). Ithaca: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
- Fiengo, R., & May, R. (1994). Indices and identity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Fiengo, R., & May, R. (2006). De Lingua Belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Grosz, B. J., Joshi, A. K., & Weinstein, S. (1995). Centering: A framework for modelling the local coherence of Discourse. Computational Linguistics, 21, 203–225.Google Scholar
- Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. thesis, University of MassachusettsGoogle Scholar
- Hobbs, J. R. (1979). Coherence and coreference. Congitive. Science, 3, 67–90.Google Scholar
- Hobbs, J. R. (1990). Literature and cognition. CSLI lecture notes 21. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Kaiser, E. (2009). Effects of anaphoric dependencies and semantic representations on pronoun interpretation. In I. Hendrickx, A. Branco, S. Lalitha Devi & R. Mitkov (Eds.), Anaphora processing and applications, Proceedings of 7th Discourse Anaphora and Anaphor Resolution Colloquium, DAARC 2009 (pp. 121–130). Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
- Kameyama, M. (1996). Indefeasible semantics and defeasible pragmatics. In M. Kanazawa, C. Pinon & H. de Swart (Eds.), Quantifiers, deduction and context (pp. 111–138). Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
- Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 1–14). Amsterdam: Mathematisch Centrum, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
- Kaplan, D. (1989a). Afterthoughts. In J. Almong, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 565–614). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Kaplan, D. (1989b). Demonstratives. In J. Almong, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Kehler, A. (2002). Coherence, reference and the theory of grammar. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
- Kendon, A. (2004). Gesture: Visible action as utterance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- King, J. C. (2014a). The metasemantics of contextual sensitivity. In A. Burgess & B. Sherman (Eds.), Metasemantics: New Essays on the Foundations of Meaning (pp. 97–118). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- King, J. C. (2014b). Speaker intentions in context. Noûs, 48, 219–237.Google Scholar
- King, J. C., & Stanley, J. (2005). Semantics, pragmatics and the role of semantic content. In Z. G. Szabó (ed.), Semantics vs. pragmatics, (pp. 111–164). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Knott, A. (1996). A data driven methodology for motivating a set of coherence relations. Ph.D. thesis, Department of Artificial Intelligence, University of Edinburgh.Google Scholar
- Kripke, S. A. (1977). Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. In P. A. French, T. E. Uehling Jr & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Studies in the Philosophy of language (pp. 255–296). University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
- Lewis, D. K. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Mann, W. C., & Thompson, S. A. (1988). Rhetorical structure theory: Toward a functional theory of text organization. Text, 8, 243–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Michaelson, E. (2013). This and that: A theory of reference for names, demonstratives, and things in between. Ph.D. thesis, UCLAGoogle Scholar
- Moens, M., & Steedman, M. (1988). Temporal ontology and temporal reference. Computational Linguistics, 14, 15–28.Google Scholar
- Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Neale, S. (2004). This, that and the other. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 68–182). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Potts, C. (2005). The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Reimer, M. (1992). Three views of demonstrative reference. Synthese, 93, 373–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Roberts, C. (2002). Demonstratives as definites. In K. van Deemter & R. Kibble (Eds.), Information sharing: Reference and presupposition in language generation and interpretation (pp. 87–137). Stanford: CSLI Press.Google Scholar
- Schiffer, S. (1981). Indexicals and the theory of reference. Synthese, 49(1), 43–100.Google Scholar
- Sidner, C. (1983). Focusing in the comprehension of definite anaphora. In M. Brady & R. C. Berwick (Eds.), Computational models of discourse (pp. 267–330). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Smyth, R. (1994). Grammatical determinants of ambiguous pronoun resolution. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 23, 197–229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Stojnić, U. (2016). Context-sensitivity in a coherent discourse. Ph.D. thesis, Rutgers Universtiy.Google Scholar
- Stojnić, U. (forthcoming). Discourse, context and coherence: The grammar of prominence. In G. Preyer (Ed.), Beyond semantics and pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Stojnić, U., Stone, M., & Lepore, E. (2013). Deixis (even without pointing). Philosophical Perspectives, 27, 502–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Stojnić U., Stone, M., & Lepore, E. (forthcoming). Distinguishing ambiguity from underspecification. In K. Turner, & L. Horn (Eds.), Pragmatics, Truth and Underspecification: Towards an Atlas of Meaning, Current Research in the Semantics/Pragmatics Interface - CRiSPI. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
- Strawson, P. F. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59, 320–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Tonhauser, J., Beaver, D., Roberts, C., & Simons, M. (2013). Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language, 89, 66–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Walker, M. A., Masayo, I., & Cote, S. (1994). Japanese discourse and the process of centering. Computational Linguistics, 20, 193–232.Google Scholar
- Webber, B. L. (1988). Tense and discourse anaphor. Computational Linguistics, 14, 61–73.Google Scholar
- Webber, B. L., Stone, M., Joshi, A., & Knott, A. (2003). Anaphora and discourse structure. Computational Linguistics, 29, 545–587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wilkins, D. (2003). Why pointing with the index finger is not a universal (in Sociocultural and Semiotic Terms). In S. Kita (Ed.), Pointing: Where language, culture and cognition meet (pp. 171–215). London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
- Winograd, T. (1972). Understanding natural language. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar