Linguistics and Philosophy

, Volume 39, Issue 4, pp 333–355 | Cite as

Three notions of dynamicness in language

Research Article

Abstract

We distinguish three ways that a theory of linguistic meaning and communication might be considered dynamic in character. We provide some examples of systems which are dynamic in some of these senses but not others. We suggest that separating these notions can help to clarify what is at issue in particular debates about dynamic versus static approaches within natural language semantics and pragmatics.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Aloni, M. (2001). Quantification under conceptual covers. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  2. Beaver, D. (2001). Presupposition and assertion in dynamic semantics. Studies in logic: Language and information. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  3. Beaver, D. (2008). As brief as possible (but no briefer). Theoretical Linguistics, 34(3), 213–228. ISSN 0301-4428.Google Scholar
  4. Beaver, D., & Geurts, B. (2014). Presupposition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter ed.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University.Google Scholar
  5. Beaver D., Krahmer E. (2001) A partial account of presupposition projection. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10: 147–182CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bittner, M. (2011). Time and modality without tenses or modals. In R. Musan & M. Rathert (Eds.), Tense across languages (pp. 147–188). Tübingen: Niemeyer.Google Scholar
  7. Bledin J. (2014) Logic informed. Mind 130(490): 277–316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bonnay, D., & Westerståhl, D. (2014). Dynamic vs. classical consequence. In A. Baltag & S. Smets (Eds.), Trends in logic, outstanding contributions: Johan F. A. K. van Benthem on logical and informational dynamics (pp. 837–854). Springer.Google Scholar
  9. Dekker P. (2012) Dynamic Semantics. Springer, DordrechtCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dever J. (2013) The revenge of the semantics–pragmatics distinction. Philosophical Perspectives 27(1): 104–144CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fox, D. (2008). Two short notes on Schlenker’s theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical Linguistics, 34, 237–252. doi:10.1515/THLI.2008.016.
  12. Gazdar G. (1979) Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition and logical form. Academic Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  13. Gillies A. (2004) Epistemic conditionals and conditional epistemics. Noûs 38(4): 585–616CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gillies A. (2007) Counterfactual scorekeeping. Linguistics and Philosophy 30(3): 329–360CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Groenendijk, J. (1999). The logic of interrogation. In T. Matthews & D. Strolovitch (Eds.), Semantics and linguistic theory IX (pp. 109–126). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1989). Context and information in dynamic semantics. In H. Bouma & B. A. G. Elsendoorm (Eds.), Working models of human perception (pp. 457–486). London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  17. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991a). Two theories of dynamic semantics. In J. van Eijck (Ed.), Logics in AI. Lectures notes in computer science (Vol. 478, pp. 55–64). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  18. Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991b). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(1), 39– 100.Google Scholar
  19. Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M., & Veltman, F. (1996). Coreference and modality. In S. Lappin (Ed.), Handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 179–213). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  20. Hamblin, C. L. (1971). Mathematical models of dialogue. Theoria, 37(2), 130–155. ISSN 1755-2567.Google Scholar
  21. Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Massachusetts.Google Scholar
  22. Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. A. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 277–322). Amsterdam: Mathematisch Centrum, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  23. Kaplan, D. (1977/1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H.Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Karttunen, L. (1969). Discourse referents. In Proceedings of the 1969 conference on computational linguistics (pp. 1–38). Berlin: Association for Computational Linguistics.Google Scholar
  25. Karttunen, L. (1974). Presupposition and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics, 1(1–3), 181–194. ISSN 0301-4428.Google Scholar
  26. Kolodny N., MacFarlane J. (2010) Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy CVII(3): 115–143CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lewis D. K. (1970) General semantics. Synthese 22(1–2): 18–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lewis, D.K. (1979) Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8(1): 339–59Google Scholar
  29. Lewis K. (2012) Discourse dynamics, pragmatics, and indefinites. Philosophical Studies 158(2): 313–342CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lewis, K. (2014). Do we need dynamic semantics? In A. Burgess & B. Sherman (Eds.), Metasemantics: New essays on the foundations of meaning (pp. 231–258). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In J. Hintikka, J.Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language: Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford workshop on grammar and semantics (pp. 221–242). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  32. Moss S. (2012) On the pragmatics of counterfactuals. Noû 46(3): 561–586CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Murray S. (2014) Varieties of update. Semantics and Pragmatics 7(2): 1–53Google Scholar
  34. Muskens, R., van Benthem, J., & Visser, A. (2011). Dynamics. In J. van Benthem & A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (2nd ed., pp. 607–670). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  35. Peters S. (1979) A truth-conditional formulation of Karttunen’s account of presupposition. Synthese 40: 301–316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Roberts, C. (1996). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In J.-H. Yoon & A. Kathol (Eds.), OSU working papers in linguistics (pp. 91–136). Columbus, OH: Department of Linguistics, The Ohio State University.Google Scholar
  37. Roberts C. (2012) Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics 5(6): 1–69Google Scholar
  38. Rothschild D. (2011) Explaining presupposition projection with dynamic semantics. Semantics and Pragmatics 4(3): 1–43Google Scholar
  39. Rothschild, D., & Yalcin, S. (2015). On the dynamics of conversation. Nous, 1–25 (Online first version). doi:10.1111/nous.12121.
  40. Schlenker P. (2007) Anti-dynamics: Presupposition projection without dynamic semantics. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16(3): 325–356CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Schlenker P. (2008) Be articulate: A pragmatic theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical Linguistics 34(3): 157–212Google Scholar
  42. Schlenker P. (2009) Local contexts. Semantics and Pragmatics 2(4): 1–78Google Scholar
  43. Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2(4), 447–457. doi:10.1007/BF00262951.
  44. Stalnaker, R. (1974). Pragmatic presuppositions. In M. K. Munitz & P. Unger (Eds.), Semantics and philosophy (pp. 197–214). New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Stalnaker R. (1975) Indicative conditionals. Philosophia 5(3): 269–286CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics (pp. 315–332). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  47. Stalnaker R. (1998) On the representation of context. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information 7: 3–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Stalnaker, R. (2002) Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(5–6): 701–21Google Scholar
  49. Stalnaker R. (2014) Context. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Valby, L. (2015). Some case studies in algebra motivated by abstract problems of language. Ph.D. Thesis, University of California, Berkeley.Google Scholar
  51. van Benthem, J. (1986). Essays in logical semantics. Studies in linguistics and philosophy. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  52. van Benthem, J. (1996). Exploring logical dynamics. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information.Google Scholar
  53. van Eijck, J., & Visser, A. (2012). Dynamic semantics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter ed.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Veltman, F. (1996) Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25(3): 221–61Google Scholar
  55. Veltman F. (2005) Making counterfactual assumptions. Journal of Semantics 22(2): 159–180CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. von Fintel, K. (2001). Counterfactuals in a dynamic context. In K. Kenstowicz (Ed.), Ken Hale: A Life in Language (pp. 123–152). Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  57. von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. (2007). An opinionated guide to epistemic modality. T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (pp. 32–62)., 2 Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  58. Willer M. (2012) A remark on iffy oughts. Journal of Philosophy 109(7): 449–461CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Willer, M. (2013a) Dynamics of epistemic modality. Philosophical Review, 122(1): 45–92Google Scholar
  60. Willer, M. (2013b). Indicative scorekeeping. In Proceedings of the 19th Amsterdam colloquium (pp. 249– 256).Google Scholar
  61. Yalcin S. (2007) Epistemic modals. Mind 116(464): 983–1026CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Yalcin, S. (2012a). Dynamic semantics. In G. Russell & D. G. Fara (Eds.), Routledge handbook of the philosophy of language (pp. 253–279). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  63. Yalcin, S. (2012b). Context probabilism. In M. Aloni, V. Kimmelman, F. Roelofsen, G. W. Sassoon, K. Schulz, & M. Westera (Eds.), Proceedings of the eighteenth Amsterdam colloquium (Vol. 7218, pp. 12–21)., Lecture notes in computer science Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  64. Yalcin, S. (2012c). A counterexample toModus Tollens. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41(6), 1001–1024.Google Scholar
  65. Yalcin S. (2015) Epistemic modality de re. Ergo 2(19): 475–527Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity College LondonLondonUK
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of CaliforniaBerkeleyUSA

Personalised recommendations