Linguistics and Philosophy

, Volume 34, Issue 6, pp 571–588 | Cite as

Sub-sentential speech and the traditional view

Research Article

Abstract

This essay argues that cases of apparently sub-sentential speech, such as Charles’ utterance of ‘a world famous topologist’ in the presence of a suitably salient woman, are unproblematic from the viewpoint of the Traditional View of meaning and truth-conditions. My argument is grounded on the distinction between different senses of ‘truth-conditions’ in double-index semantics, and on an understanding of semantic inputs as constraints on logical forms. Given these conceptual resources, I argue that an utterly traditional understanding of the relationships between meaning and truth yields the intuitively desired results.

Keywords

Semantics Pragmatics Truth-conditional pragmatics 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Cappelen H., Lepore E. (2007) The myth of unarticulated constituents. In: O’Rourke M., Washington C. (eds) Situating semantics: Essays on the philosophy of John Perry. MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  2. Carston R. (1988) Implicature, explicature, and truth-theoretic semantics. In: Kempson R. (eds) Mental representations. Cambridge University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  3. Clapp L. (2005) On the interpretation and performance of nonsentential assertion. In: Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (eds) Ellipsis and nonsentential speech. Springer, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  4. Crimmins M., Perry J. (1989) The Prince and the Phone-Booth. Journal of Philosophy 86: 685–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (2001) Logical Form and the Vernacular. Mind and Language 16(4): 393–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (2004) Shorthand, syntactic ellipsis, and the pragmatic determinants of what is said. Mind and Language 19(4): 442–471CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (2005) Introduction. In: Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (eds) Ellipsis and nonsentential speech. Springer, Berlin, pp 1–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Grice P. (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  9. Hornstein N. (1995) Logical form: From GB to minimalism. Blackwell, Malden, MAGoogle Scholar
  10. Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives. Manuscript. Reprinted in J. Almog et al. (eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford University Press, 1989.Google Scholar
  11. Kenyon T. (2005) Nonsentences, implicature, and success in communication. In: Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (eds) Ellipsis and nonsentential speech. Springer, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  12. Ludlow P. (2005) A note on alleged cases of non-sentential assertion. In: Elugardo R., Stainton R.J. (eds) Ellipsis and nonsentential speech. Springer, Berlin, pp 95–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Perry J. (1986) Thought without representation. Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 60: 137–152Google Scholar
  14. Perry, J. (1998). Indexicals, contexts and unarticulated constituents. In Proceedings of the 1995 CSLIAmsterdam logic, language and computation conference. CSLI Publications, Stanford, CA.Google Scholar
  15. Perry J. (2001) Reference and reflexivity. CSLI Publications, Stanford, CAGoogle Scholar
  16. Predelli S. (2005) Contexts: Meaning, truth-conditions, and the use of language. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  17. Recanati F. (2002) Unarticulated constituents. Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 299–345CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Recanati F. (2003) Literal meaning. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Searle J. (1980) The background of meaning. In: Searle J.R., Kiefer F., Bierwisch M. (eds) Speech Act theory and pragmatics. Reidel Publishing Company, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  20. Sperber D., Wilson D. (1986) Relevance: Communication and cognition. London–Oxford, Wiley–BlackwellGoogle Scholar
  21. Stainton R. (1997) Utterance meaning and syntactic ellipsis. Pragmatics and Cognition 5: 51–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Stainton R. (1997) What assertion is not. Philosophical Studies 85: 57–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Stainton R. (2004) Defense of non-sentential assertion. In: Szabo Z. (eds) Semantics vs. pragmatics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 383–457Google Scholar
  24. Stainton R. (2005) The pragmatics of non-sentences. In: Horn L.R., Ward G. (eds) The handbook of pragmatics. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  25. Stainton R. (2006) Words and thoughts: Subsentences, ellipsis, and the philosophy of language. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  26. Stanley J. (2000) Context and logical form. Linguistics and Philosophy 234: 391–434CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Travis C. (1985) On what is strictly speaking true. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15(2): 187–229Google Scholar
  28. Travis C. (1996) Meaning’s role in truth. Mind 105: 451–466CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Travis C. (1997) Pragmatics. In: Hale B., Wright C. (eds) A companion to the philosophy of language. Blackwell Publishers, OxfordGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of NottinghamNottinghamUK

Personalised recommendations