Advertisement

Journal of Logic, Language and Information

, Volume 27, Issue 4, pp 313–341 | Cite as

Intertheoretic Reduction, Confirmation, and Montague’s Syntax-Semantics Relation

  • Kristina Liefke
  • Stephan Hartmann
Article

Abstract

Intertheoretic relations are an important topic in the philosophy of science. However, since their classical discussion by Ernest Nagel, such relations have mostly been restricted to relations between pairs of theories in the natural sciences. This paper presents a case study of a new type of intertheoretic relation that is inspired by Montague’s analysis of the linguistic syntax-semantics relation. The paper develops a simple model of this relation. To motivate the adoption of our new model, we show that this model extends the scope of application of the Nagelian (or related) models and that it shares the epistemological advantages of the Nagelian model. The latter is achieved in a Bayesian framework.

Keywords

Intertheoretic relations Reduction Montague semantics Syntax-semantics relation Philosophy of linguistics Bayesian confirmation 

Notes

Acknowledgements

We wish to thank Lucas Champollion, Paul Egré, Branden Fitelson, Greg Novack, Peter Pagin, Jan Sprenger, Markus Werning, Rineke Verbrugge, and three anonymous reviewers for JoLLI for valuable input about the content of this paper. We owe our audiences at the Future of Philosophy of Science Conference, FEW 11, Bridges 2014, and the Tokyo Forum for Analytic Philosophy for many helpful comments and suggestions. The research for this paper has been supported by Tilburg University (via K. Liefke’s doctoral fellowship), the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation (via S. Hartmann’s Humboldt Professorship), and the German Research Foundation (via K. Liefke’s grant LI 2562/1-1).

References

  1. Ajdukiewicz, K. (1935). Die syntaktische Konnexität. Studia Philosophica, 1, 1–27.Google Scholar
  2. Bach, E. (1976). An extension of classical transformational grammar. In R. Saenz (ed.), Proceedings of the 1976 conference Problems of Linguistic Metatheory (pp. 183–224). Michigan: Michigan State University.Google Scholar
  3. Bartsch, R., & Vennemann, T. (1972). Semantic structures. Frankfurt: Athenäum.Google Scholar
  4. Bickle, J. (2006). Reducing mind to molecular pathways: Explicating the reductionism implicit in current cellular and molecular neuroscience. Synthese, 151, 411–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  6. Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4, 20–40; reprinted in Meaning and Necessity: a study in semantics and modal logic, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London (1988).Google Scholar
  7. Carnap, R. (1968). Logische syntax der sprache. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chierchia, G., & Turner, R. (1988). Semantics and property theory. Linguistics and Philosophy, 11(3), 261–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chomsky, N. (2000). Linguistics and brain science. In A. Marantz, Y. Miyashita, & W. O’Neil (Eds.), Image, language, brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Chomsky, N., & Structure, D. (1971). Surface structure, and semantic representation. In D. Steinberg & L. Jakobovits (Eds.), Semantics: an interdisciplinary reader. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Church, A. (1940). A formulation of the simple theory of types. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5(2), 56–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cresswell, M. J. (1973). Logics and languages. London: Methuen Young Books.Google Scholar
  13. Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 44(1), 43–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dizadji-Bahmani, F., Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Who’s afraid of Nagelian reduction? Erkenntnis, 73(3), 393–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dizadji-Bahmani, F., Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2011). Confirmation and reduction: A Bayesian account. Synthese, 179(2), 321–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or bust?. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Eberle, R. A. (1971). Replacing one theory by another under preservation of a given feature. Philosophy of Science, 38(4), 486–501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Eells, E., & Fitelson, B. (2000). Measuring confirmation and evidence. The Journal of Philosophy, 97(12), 663–672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fitelson, B. (1999). The plurality of Bayesian measures of confirmation and the problem of measure sensitivity. Philosophy of Science, 66, 362–378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Forbes, G. (Forthcoming). Content and theme in attitude ascriptions. In A. Grzankowski & M. Montague (eds.), Non-propositional intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hájek, A., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Bayesian epistemology. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology. Malden, MA: Blackwell Companions to Philosophy.Google Scholar
  22. Hartman, J. (2012). Varieties of clausal complementation. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  23. Hartmann, S. (1999). Models and stories in hadron physics. In M. S. Morgan & M. Morrison (Eds.), Models as mediators (pp. 326–346). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hartmann, S., & Sprenger, J. (2010). Bayesian epistemology. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Routledge companion to epistemology. Malden, MA: Routledge.Google Scholar
  25. Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  26. Hendriks, H. (1990). Flexible Montague grammar. Amsterdam: ITLI Prepublication Series for Logic, Semantics and Philosophy of Language.Google Scholar
  27. Hendriks, H. (1993). Studied flexibility: Categories and types in syntax and semantics. Doctoral dissertation, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
  28. Hoover, K. D. (2010). Idealizing reduction: The microfoundations of macroeconomics. Erkenntnis, 73(3), 329–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (2005). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  30. Kastner, I. (2015). Factivity mirrors interpretation: The selectional requirements of presuppositional verbs. Lingua, 164(Part A), 156–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Kemeny, J. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1967). On reduction. Philosophical Studies, 19, 6–19.Google Scholar
  32. Kuipers, T. A. F. (1982). The reduction of phenomenological to kinetic thermostatics. Philosophy of Science, 49(1), 107–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Levins, R., & Lewontin, R. (1980). Dialectics and reductionism in ecology. Synthese, 43, 47–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22(1–2), 18–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Litosseliti, L. (Ed.). (2010). Research methods in linguistics. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  36. Mitchell, S. D. (2003). Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Montague, R. (1976a). English as a formal language. In R. H. Thomason (Ed.), Formal philosophy: Selected papers of Richard Montague. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Montague, R. (1976b). Universal grammar. In R. H. Thomason (Ed.), Formal philosophy: Selected papers of Richard Montague. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Montague, R. (1976c). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In R. H. Thomason (Ed.), Formal philosophy: Selected papers of Richard Montague. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  40. Moortgat, M. (1997). Categorial type logics. In J. van Benthem & A. G. B. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers.Google Scholar
  41. Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  42. Nagel, E. (1977). Teleology revisited. The Journal of Philosophy, 84, 261–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Neapolitan, R. (2003). Learning Bayesian networks. New York: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  44. Partee, B. (1987). Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In J. Groenendijk, D. de Jong, & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.Google Scholar
  45. Partee, B. (1997). Montague grammar. In J. van Benthem & A. G. B. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers.Google Scholar
  46. Pearl, J. (1988). Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems: Networks of plausible inference. San Francisco: Morgan Kauffman.Google Scholar
  47. Podesva, R. J., & Sharma, D. (Eds.). (2013). Research methods in linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Poeppel, D., & Embick, D. (2005). Defining the relation between linguistics and neuroscience. In A. Cutler (Ed.), Twenty-first century psycholinguistics: Four cornerstones. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  49. Potts, C. (2002). The lexical semantics of parenthetical-as and appositive-which. Syntax, 5(1), 55–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Rasinger, S. M. (2013). Quantitative research in linguistics: An introduction. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  51. Sag, I., Wasow, T., & Bender, E. (2003). Syntactic theory: A formal approach. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  52. Schaffner, K. F. (1967). Approaches to reduction. Philosophy of Science, 34, 137–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Schaffner, K. F. (1974). Reductionism in biology: Prospects and problems. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (pp. 613–632).Google Scholar
  54. Schaffner, K. F. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago: Science and its Conceptual Foundations, The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  55. Schouten, M., & de Jong, H. L. (Eds.). (2012). The matter of the mind: Philosophical essays of psychology, neuroscience, and reduction. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  56. Takahashi, S. (2010). The hidden side of clausal complements. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 28(2), 343–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Tarski, A., Mostowski, A., & Robinson, R. M. (1953). Undecidable theories. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
  58. Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Biology, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for LinguisticsGoethe University FrankfurtFrankfurt am MainGermany
  2. 2.Munich Center for Mathematical PhilosophyLudwig-Maximilians-University MunichMunichGermany

Personalised recommendations