Journal of Logic, Language and Information

, Volume 24, Issue 2, pp 193–209 | Cite as

Logic Reduced To Bare (Proof-Theoretical) Bones

Article
  • 136 Downloads

Abstract

What is a minimal proof-theoretical foundation of logic? Two different ways to answer this question may appear to offer themselves: reduce the whole of logic either to the relation of inference, or else to the property of incompatibility. The first way would involve defining logical operators in terms of the algebraic properties of the relation of inference—with conjunction \(\hbox {A}\wedge \hbox {B}\) as the infimum of A and B, negation \(\lnot \hbox {A}\) as the minimal incompatible of A, etc. The second way involves introducing logical operators in terms of the relation of incompatibility, such that X is incompatible with \(\{\lnot \hbox {A}\}\) iff every Y incompatible with X is incompatible with {A}; and X is incompatible with \(\{\hbox {A}\!\wedge \!\hbox {B}\}\) iff X is incompatible with {A,B}; etc. Whereas the first route leads us naturally to intuitionistic logic, the second leads us to classical logic. The aim of this paper is threefold: to investigate the relationship of the two approaches within a very general framework, to discuss the viability of erecting logic on such austere foundations, and to find out whether choosing one of the ways we are inevitably led to a specific logical system.

Keywords

Inference Incompatibility Proof theory Intuitionistic logic 

References

  1. Belnap, N., & Massey, A. (1990). Semantic holism. Studia Logica, 49, 67–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Brandom, R., & Aker, A. (2008). Appendix to Chapter 5. In R. Brandom: Between saying and doing: Towards analytical pragmatism (pp. 141–175). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Carnap, R. (1934). Logische Syntax der Sprache. Vienna: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. (1943). Formalization of logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Carnap, R. (1946). Modalities and quantification. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 11, 33–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chellas, B. F. (1980). Modal logic: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dummett, M. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Garson, J. W. (2013). What logics mean. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gentzen, G. (1934). Untersuchungen über das logische Schliessen I. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 39, 176–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gentzen, G. (1936). Untersuchungen über das logische Schliessen II. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 41, 405–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Koslow, A. (1992). A structuralist theory of logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Lorenzen, P. (1955). Einführung in die operative Logik und Mathematik. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Peregrin, J. (2008). What is the logic of inference? Studia Logica, 88, 263–294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Peregrin, J. (2010). Inferentializing semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39, 255–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Peregrin, J. (2011). Logic as based on incompatibility. In M. Peliš & V. Punčochář (Eds.), The logica yearbook 2010 (pp. 158–167). London: College Publications.Google Scholar
  17. Restall, G. (2009). Truth values and proof theory. Studia Logica, 92, 241–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Punčochář, V. (2012). Some modifications of Carnap’s modal logic. Studia Logica, 100, 517–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Scott, D. (1971). On engendering an illusion of understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 787–807.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Scott, D. S. (1972). Background to formalization. In H. Leblanc (Ed.), Truth, syntax and modality (pp. 244–273). Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
  21. Shapiro, S. (1991). Foundations without foundationalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  22. Thomason, S. K. (1973). A new representation of S5. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 14, 281–284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute of PhilosophyAcademy of Sciences of the Czech RepublicPragueCzech Republic

Personalised recommendations