Skip to main content
Log in

The Naturalizing Error

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We describe an error type that we call the naturalizing error: an appeal to nature as a self-justified description dictating or limiting our choices in moral, economic, political, and other social contexts. Normative cultural perspectives may be subtly and subconsciously inscribed into purportedly objective descriptions of nature, often with the apparent warrant and authority of science, yet not be fully warranted by a systematic or complete consideration of the evidence. Cognitive processes may contribute further to a failure to notice the lapses in scientific reasoning and justificatory warrant. By articulating this error type at a general level, we hope to raise awareness of this pervasive error type and to facilitate critiques of claims that appeal to what is “natural” as inevitable or unchangeable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ironically, perhaps, this approach respects Bloor (1991) principle of symmetry, by coupling a sociological understanding of false beliefs (error) with a corresponding sociological understanding of the complementary processes that yield correct claims. See especially Bloor’s response to critics (1991, 175–179).

References

  • Allchin, D. (2001). Error types. Perspectives on Science, 9, 38–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2006). Male, female and/or—? American Biology Teacher, 68, 372–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2007a). A more fitting analogy. American Biology Teacher, 69, 174–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2007b). Teaching science lawlessly. In P. Heering & D. Osewold (Eds.), Constructing scientific understanding through contextual teaching (pp. 13–31). Berlin: Frank & Timme.

  • Allchin, D. (2012). To be human. American Biology Teacher, 75(2), 132–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2014). Organisms, modified, genetically. American Biology Teacher, 76, 639–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala, F. (1970). Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 37, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barkan, E. (1992). The retreat of scientific racism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1991). Knowledge and social imagery (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolhuis, J. J., Brown, G. R., Richardson, R. C., & Laland, K. N. (2011). Darwin in mind: New opportunities for evolutionary psychology. PLoS Biology, 9(7), e1001109. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brem, S. K., Ranney, M., & Schindel, J. (2003). Perceived consequences of evolution: College students perceive negative personal and social impact in evolutionary theory. Science Education, 87, 181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, J. (1995). Charles Darwin: Voyaging. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. J. (2005). Adapting minds: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (1995). The evolution of desire: Strategies of human mating. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (2007). The evolution of human mating. Acta Psychologica Sinica, 39(3), 505–512.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canetto, S. S. (1996). What is a normal family? Common assumptions and current evidence. Journal of Primary Prevention, 17, 31–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, A. C. (2015). The natural family where it belongs: New Agrarian essays. Piscataway: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, A. C., & Mero, P. T. (2007). The natural family: A manifesto. Dallas: Spence. See also http://familymanifesto.net.

  • Carlson, A. C., & Mero, P. T. (2008). The natural family: Bulwark of liberty. Piscataway: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrera-Bastos, P., Fontes-Villalba, M., O’Keefe, J. H., Lindeberg, S., & Cordain, L. (2011). The western diet and lifestyle and diseases of civilization. Research Reports in Clinical Cardiology, 2, 15–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L., & Stolleis, M. ( Eds). (2008). Natural law and laws of nature in early modern Europe. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1995). God’s utility function. Scientific American, 273(5), 80–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The god delusion. New York: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, A., & Moore, J. (1994). Darwin: The life of a tormented evolutionist. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, J. (1992). The third chimpanzee. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etcoff, N. (1999). Survival of the prettiest. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fee, E. (1979). Nineteenth-century craniology: The study of the female skull. Bulletin of the History of Medicine, 53, 415–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1969). The triumph of the Darwinian method. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T. (1991). How we know what isn’t so. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez Galli, L. M., & Meinardi, E. N. (2010). The role of teleological thinking in learning the Darwinian model of evolution. Evolution: Education and Outreach, 4(1), 145–152. doi:10.1007/s12052-010-0272-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1996). The mismeasure of man (2D ed.). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in the world of modern science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. (1991). Whose science? Whose knowledge?: Thinking from women’s lives. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1894/1989). Evolution and ethics (Facsimile reprint). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Giraud & Strauss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D. (2004). Are children “intuitive theists”? Psychological Science, 15, 295–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D., & Rosset, E. (2009). The human function compunction: Teleological explanation in adults. Cognition, 11, 138–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohler, W. (1966). The place of value in a world of facts. New York: Mentor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland, R. N., & Brown, G. R. (2002). Sense and nonsense: Evolutionary perspectives on human behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, C. S. (2003). Equality for the sexes in human evolution? Early hominid dimorphism and implications for mating systems and social behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 100(16), 9103–9104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C., Rose, S., & Kamin, L. J. (1984). Not in our genes: Biology, ideology and human nature. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, D. E. (2013). The story of the human body: Evolution, health, and disease. New York: Pantheon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansfield, H. (2006). Manliness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principa Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. (2002). What genes can’t do. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review Of General Psychology, 2, 175–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, J. D. (2004). A major evolutionary transition to more than two sexes? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 19, 83–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, R. A. (1998). Perceiving facts and values. Philosophy, 73, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2002). The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy and other essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (2003). Darwin on minds, morals, and emotions. In J. Hodge & G. Radick (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Darwin (pp. 92–115). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, R. C. (2007). Evolutionary psychology as maladapted psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (1996). The origins of virtue. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (2010). The rational optimist: How prosperity evolves. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, S. (2003). Lifelines: Life beyond the gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbloom, C. (2014). Popular diets and athletes: Premises, promises, pros, and pitfalls of diets and what athletes should know about diets and sports performance. Nutrition Today, 49(5), 244–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, J. (2004). Evolution’s rainbow: Diversity, gender, and sexuality in nature and people. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samaras, T. (2007). Human body size and the laws of scaling: Physiological, performance, growth, longevity, and ecological ramifications. Hauppage: Nova Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiebinger, L. (1989). The mind has no sex? Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiebinger, L. (1993). Why mammals are called mammals: Gender politics in eighteenth-century natural history. The American Historical Review, 98(2), 382–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanahan, M. (1994). Unnatural history? Star Tribune, 26 August, 16A.

  • Sigmund, K., & Hilbe, C. (2011). Darwin and the evolution of human cooperation. In H. Meyer-Ortmanns & S. Thurner (Eds.), Principles of evolution (pp. 331–347). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. E. (1993). The Standard North American family: SNAF as an ideological code. Journal of Family Issues, 14, 50–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinle, F. (2008). From principles to regularities: Tracing “laws of nature” in early modern France and England. In L. Daston & M. Stolleis (Eds.), Natural law and laws of nature in early modern Europe (pp. 215–232). Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stepan, N. (1982). The idea of race in science. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, S. (1992). Irrationality: Why we don’t think straight. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wijngaard, M. (1997). Reinventing the sexes: The biomedical construction of femininity and masculinity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. (1975). Darwin’s Metaphor: Nature’s place in Victorian culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuk, M. (2013). Paleofantasy: What evolution really tells us about sex, diet, and how we live. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Douglas Allchin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Allchin, D., Werth, A.J. The Naturalizing Error. J Gen Philos Sci 48, 3–18 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-016-9336-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-016-9336-x

Keywords

Navigation