Abstract
Is food’s naturalness conceptually connected to its healthiness? Answering the question requires spelling out the following: (1) What is meant by the healthiness of food? (2) What different conceptual meanings the term natural has in the context of food? (3) Are some of those meanings connected to the healthiness of food? In this paper the healthiness of food is understood narrowly as food’s accordance with nutritional needs of its eater. The connection of healthiness to the following five food-related senses of the term “natural’’ is analyzed: naturalness as nutritive suitability, naturalness as moderate need satisfaction, naturalness as lack of human influence, naturalness as authenticity, and naturalness as familiarity. It is concluded that some very common current uses of the term “natural,” such as naturalness as lack of human influence, are not conceptually connected to the healthiness of food. Nevertheless, the first two senses of naturalness are strongly conceptually connected to healthiness in the food context and the last one may be indirectly related to it. Thus, desire for natural food is not necessarily mistaken and misguided.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
However, there are exceptions such as some modern baby milk substitutes that satisfy all nutritional needs of a newborn baby (and that are food products in the sense of being eatable outcomes of human labor).
In practice, there is usually no limit or criterion to define the reference group (i.e., the group of people that the concept of healthy food refers to) and, thus, the healthiness of food also is relational to choices made regarding it (for further discussion see for example Boorse 1977; Döring et al. 2012).
Naturalness as moderate need satisfaction as described here leaves open the status of those actions that neither contribute to need satisfaction nor work against it. Should those actions be considered natural, unnatural, or falling outside the scope of naturalness as moderate need satisfaction? Or should all human actions—even such as car driving or movie watching—be seen at least indirectly to work for or against the agent’s needs?
I thank one of the anonymous referees for pointing this out for me.
For further discussion on the distinction between absolute and relative senses of naturalness see Siipi (2008).
From the point of view of marketing, many naturalness claims in food advertisements and labels are semantically empty in the sense of lacking any particular meaning. Similarly to the famous slogan “Coca-Cola is it,” they are not meant to refer to any particular property or quality of the product. Rather they merely carry a positive connotation to which consumers are free to associate their own values and desires regarding the product. Thus, to a great extent the question regarding possible meanings of naturalness claims in food advertisements and labels concerns the meanings consumers may attach to them.
References
Angermeier, P. (2000). Natural imperative for biological conservation. Conservation Biology, 14(2), 373–381.
Bergin, L. A. (2009). Latina feminist metaphysics and genetically engineered foods. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 22(3), 257–271.
Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44(4), 542–573.
Brennan, A. (1988). Thinking about nature: An investigation on nature, value and ecology. Chatham: Mackays of Chatman PLC.
Budiansky, S. (1992). The covenant of the wild: Why animals chose domestication. London: Phoenix.
Burghess, J. A., & Walsh, A. J. (1998). Is genetic engineering wrong, Per Se? Journal of Value Inquiry, 32(3), 393–406.
Callicott, J. B. (1995). Animal liberation: A triangular affair. In C. Pierce & D. Van De Veer (Eds.), People, penguins, and plastic trees (pp. 237–254). Belmont: Wadsworth.
Chadwick, R. (2000). Novel, natural, nutritious: Towards a philosophy of food. Proceeding of the Aristotelian Society, 100, 193–208.
Cooley, D. R., & Goreham, G. A. (2004). Are transgenic organisms unnatural. Ethics and the Environment, 9(1), 46–55.
D’Silva, J. (1995). A critical view of the genetic engineering of farm animals. In P. Wheale & R. McNally (Eds.), Animal genetic engineering: Of pigs, oncomice and men. London: Pluto Press.
Döring, T. F., Pautasso, M., Finckh, M. R., & Wolfe, M. S. (2012). Concepts of plant health—Reviewing and challenging the foundations of plant protection. Plant Pathology, 61(1), 1–15.
Frazier, K. (2010). Natural low carb diet. Retrieved 15 May. http://www.livestrong.com/article/298363-natural-low-carb-diet/.
Freston, K. (2009). Shattering the meat myth: Humans are natural vegetarians. Huffpost healthy living. Retrieved 14 June 2012. http://www.huffingtonpost.com/kathy-freston/shattering-the-meat-myth_b_214390.html.
Gregory, N., & Gregory, R. (2010). A values-based framework for community food choices. Environmental Values, 19(1), 99–119.
Häyry, M. (1994). Categorical objections to genetic engineering—A critique. In A. Dyson & J. Harris (Eds.), Ethics and biotechnology (pp. 202–215). London: Routledge.
Häyry, M., & Häyry, H. (1989). Ihmisoikeudet, moraali ja lisääntymisen vapaus. In H. Häyry & M. Häyry (Eds.), Luonnotonta lastensaantia (pp. 174–195). Helsinki: Gaudeamus.
Huber, M., Rembiałkowska, E., Średnicka, D., Bügel, S., & van de Vijver, L. P. L. (2011). Organic food and impact on human health: Assessing the status quo and prospects of research. NJAS—Wageningen Journal of Life Sciences, 58(1), 103–109.
Hunter, M. (1996). Benchmarks for managing ecosystems: Are human activities natural? Conservation Biology, 10(3), 695–697.
Johnson, L. (2011). How to avoid processed foods in a healthy diet. Retrieved 15 May. http://www.cbn.com/cbnnews/healthscience/2010/june/how-to-avoid-processed-foods-in-a-healthy-diet-/.
Kaplan, D. M. (2012). Introduction: The philosophy of food. In D. M. Kaplan (Ed.), The philosophy of food (pp. 1–23). Berkeley: University of California Press.
Kingma, E. (2007). What it is to be healthy. Analysis, 67(294), 128–133.
Korzen, S., Sandøe, P., & Larsen, J. (2011). Pure meat—Public perceptions of risk reduction strategies in meat production. Food Policy, 36(2), 158–165.
L’Abbe, M. R., Stender, S., Skeaff, C. M., Ghafoorunissa, & Tavella, M. (2009). Approaches to removing trans fats from the food supply in industrialized and developing countries. European Journal of Clinical Nutrition, 63(1), 50–67.
Lemoine, M. (2009). The meaning and opposition between healthy and pathological. Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy, 12(3), 335–362.
Levy, D. (1980). Perversion and unnaturalness as moral categories. Ethics, 90(2), 191–202.
Loren, K. (2012). Natural milk vs. processed milk. Retrieved 16 May. http://www.karlloren.com/milk.htm.
Madsen, K. H., Holm, P. B., Larsen, J., & Sandøe, P. (2003). Ranking genetically modified plants according to familiarity. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 15(3), 267–278.
Margetts, B. M., Martinez, J. A., Saba, A., Holm, L., & Kearney, M. (1997). Definitions of “healthy” eating: A pan-EU survey of consumer attitudes to food, nutrition and health. European Journal of Clinical Nutrition, 51, 23–29.
Mathews, E. (1988). AIDS and sexual morality. Bioethics, 2(2), 119–128.
Matt, D., Rembialkowska, E., Luik, A., Peetsman, E., & Pehme, S. (2011). Quality of organic vs. conventional food and effects on health. Estonian university of life sciences. Retrieved 10 May 2012. http://orgprints.org/19504/1/Report_2011_%281%29.pdf.
McKibben, B. (1989). The end of nature. New York: Random House.
Meijboom, F. L. B. (2007). Trust, food, and health. Questions of trust at the interface between food and health. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20(3), 231–245.
Midgley, M. (1995). Sidelight: Do what’s natural, you say? In C. Pierce & D. Van De Veer (Eds.), People, penguins and plastic trees (pp. 103–105). Belmont: Wadsworth.
Mill, J. S. (1969). Essays on ethics, religion and society. Toronto: Toronto University Press.
Mullin, G. E. (2010). Popular diets prescribed by alternative practitioners—Part 2. Nutrition in Clinical Practice, 25(3), 308–309.
Nordenfelt, L. (2002). On health and natural functions. In A. Gimmler, C. Lenk, & G. Aumüller (Eds.), Health and quality of life (pp. 19–26). Münster: Lit Verlag.
Nordenfelt, L. (2006). Animal and human health and welfare: A comparative philosophical analysis. Wallingford: CAB International.
Nordenfelt, L. (2007). The concepts of health and illness revisited. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 10(1), 5–10.
Önning, G., Åkesson, B., Öste, R., & Lundquist, I. (1998). Effects of consumption of oat milk, soya milk, or cow’s milk on plasma lipids and antioxidative capacity in healthy subjects. Annals of Nutrition & Metabolism, 42(4), 211–220.
Östlund, L., Ahlberg, L., Zackrisson, O., Bergman, I., & Arno, S. (2009). Bark-peeling, food stress and tree spirits—The use of pine inner bark for food in scandinavia and North America. Journal of Ethnobiology, 29(1), 94–112.
Pouteau, S. (2002). The food debate: Ethical versus substantial equivalence. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 15(3), 291–303.
Räikkä, J., & Rossi, K. (2002). Geenit ja etiikka: Kysymyksiä uuden geeniteknologian arvoista. Helsinki: WSOY.
Richards, J. R. (1984). The sceptical feminist: A philosophical enquiry. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Rolston, H., I. I. I. (1979). Can and ought we to follow nature. Environmental Ethics, 1(1), 7–30.
Rozin, P. (2005). Meaning of ‘natural’: Process more important than content. Psychological Science, 16, 652–658.
Rozin, P., Spranca, M., Krieger, Z., Nauhaus, R., Surillo, D., Swerdlin, A., et al. (2004). Preference for natural: Instrumental and ideational/moral motivations, and the contrast between foods and medicine. Appetite, 43(2), 147–154.
Sacks, F. M., Lichtenstein, A., Van Horn, L., Harris, W., Kris-Etherton, P., & Winson, M. (2006). Soy protein, isoflavones, and cardiovascular health. Circulation, 113, 1033–1044.
Sagoff, M. (2001). Genetic engineering and the concept of the natural. Philosophy and the Policy Quarterly, 21(1), 2–10.
Saher, M. (2006). Everyday beliefs about food and health. Helsinki: Yliopistopaino.
Schramme, T. (2007). Lennart Nordenfelt’s theory of health: Introduction to the theme. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 10(1), 3–4.
Scott-Thomas, C. (2009). US consumers think that natural is greener than organic, says survey. Food Navigator-USA, 6 July 2009. Retrieved April 24 2011. http://www.foodnavigator-usa.com/Financial-Industry/US-consumers-think-natural-is-greener-than-organic-says-survey.
Scrinis, G. (2008). On the ideology of nutritionism. Gastronomica: The Journal of Food and Culture, 8(1), 39–48.
Scrinis, G. (2012). Nutritionism and functional foods. In D. Kaplan (Ed.), The philosophy of food. California: University of California Press.
Siipi, H. (2003). Artefacts and living artefacts. Environmental Values, 12(4), 413–430.
Siipi, H. (2008). Dimensions of naturalness. Ethics and the Environment, 1(1), 71–103.
Smith, R. (2002). In search of a “non-disease”. BMJ, 324(883), 1.
Stitt, S. (1996). An international perspective on food and cooking skills in education. British Food Journal, 98(10), 27–34.
Stone, C. D. (1972). Should trees have standing?—Towards legal rights for natural objects. Southern California Law Review, 45, 450–501.
Tenbült, P., de Vries, N. K., Dreezens, E., & Martijn, C. (2005). Perceived naturalness and acceptance of genetically modified food. Appetite, 45(1), 47–50.
Thompson, D. B., & McDonald, B. (forthcoming). What food is “Good’’ for you? Toward a pragmatic consideration of multiple values domains. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. Online first.
Townsend, A. R., Howarth, R. W., Bazzaz, F. A., Booth, M. S., Cleveland, C. C., Collinge, S. K., et al. (2003). Human health effects of a changing global nitrogen cycle. Frontiers in Ecology and the Environment, 1(5), 240–246.
Tulloch, A. (2005). What do we mean by health? British Journal of General Practice, April 2005, 320–323.
Verhoog, H., Matze, M., van Beuren, E. L., & Baars, T. (2003). The role of the concept of natural (naturalness) in organic farming. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 16(1), 29–49.
Verhoog, H., Van Beuren, E. T. L., Matze, M., & Baars, T. (2007). The Value of `naturalness’ in organic agriculture. NJAS—Wageningen Journal of Life Sciences, 54(4), 333–345.
WHO (1948). Preamble to the constitution of the World Health Organization as adopted by the International Health Conference, New York, 19-22 June, 1946; signed on 22 July 1946 by the representatives of 61 states (Official Records of the World Health Organization, no. 2, p. 100) and entered into force on 7 April 1948. Retrieved 10 May. http://www.who.int/about/definition/en/print.html.
Wong, C. (2011). Raw food diet. Retrieved 15 May 2012. http://altmedicine.about.com/od/popularhealthdiets/a/Raw_Food.htm.
Acknowledgments
I want to thank Peter Sandøe and anonymous referees for their useful comments on the earlier versions of this paper, Susanne Uusitalo for correcting my English, and Academy of Finland for the financial support.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Siipi, H. Is Natural Food Healthy?. J Agric Environ Ethics 26, 797–812 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-012-9406-y
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-012-9406-y
Keywords
- Food
- Natural
- Healthy
- Conceptual analysis