Abstract
I start with a detailed but partial analysis of a case regarding grade inflation. The case is inspired by the discussion in Crumbley et al. (2010) and its elaboration in Roberts (2016). I supplement the case description by introducing certain facts that are not in the original discussion. The subsequent analysis is based on this enriched case description. I then raise a number of objections against my analysis. An important metaethical, methodological question emerges while responding to these objections. To what extent are characterizations of moral situations and their descriptions independent from moral commitments? Is there a neutral concept of moral relevance? I argue that we do not have a theory-neutral concept of moral relevance, and that case descriptions essentially presuppose moral commitments. From my moral perspective, as this perspective is reflected in the enriched case description I utilize, the original case description of grade inflation already involves utilizing the wrong moral perspective or theory.
This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.
Notes
“Student evaluations of teaching do not measure teaching effectiveness. Furthermore, they are influenced by several factors unrelated to teaching quality such as minority status, foreign accent and gender of instructors, and the discipline they are teaching. This makes their use by university administrators in decisions about hiring, salary increases, and promotions unfair and potentially illegal.” (p. 283).
“One way that we might expect to see students following this consumerist approach would be by enrolling in easier courses in order to obtain high grades, while expending minimal effort. While our own estimates cannot test all components of the consumerist framework, the positive impact of Easy in the fixed effects results suggests that sections taught by instructors perceived as easier fill more quickly, as proposed in our second hypothesis.” (Brown & Kosovich 2015, p. 506).
“… after the addition of weekly objective, rigorously developed MC tests and more precise grading rubrics, the distribution of final course grades revealed a downward shift. Whereas A was the original modal grade, now, A- is the modal grade, followed by B + , and the percentage of C grades has more than doubled. Bickes and Schim…found that adding objective grading rubrics to their nursing course decreased the percentage of A grades from 88 to 49% but more than doubled the percentage of C grades (7%-15%). Findings from this study suggest that the addition of precise rubrics and valid quality MC test in this graduate research course may have led to the downward shift in grades. Such distributions may be less inflated and more commensurate with student knowledge acquisition.” (White & Heitzler 2018, p. 76).
In discussion.
There is a further complication here I will not pursue beyond this brief note. What one should further discuss is whether these are cases of concealment that cause harm, even if they are cases of concealment. There is no doubt that there are instances of concealment which are not considered to cause harm (or perhaps cause more benefit than harm). I have not seen articles in applied ethics journals about the immorality of espionage or data security engineering, although both professions practice concealment. If concealment is not seen as causing harm and thus being morally questionable in all its instantiations, we then need an argument that concealment in a particular case causes harm (or more harm than benefit) before we can conclude that practicing it is morally problematic. The move from concealment to harm is not justifiable without further argumentation.
Rescher (2015) is a very stimulating discussion of the concept of excellence.
I cannot refrain from pointing out that the analysis of the concept of harm, characterizing interests without appealing to preconceived moral assumptions, and the epistemology of detecting the interests of others are some very important issues we are bypassing. There is prima facie evidence that students do not consider inflated grades as harming their interests. (Shaughnessy et al., 2004) The belief that we know others’ interest better than they do is a prime instance of paternalistic ethics, instances of which are widely discussed in the Ethics literature. Of course this problem also arises for other stakeholders in the case, such as parents and administrators.
“The policy change followed the determination of a university committee that "it is desirable for Cornell University to provide more information to the reader of a transcript and produce more meaningful letter grades." Curbing grade inflation was not explicitly stated as a goal of this policy. Instead, the stated rationale was that "students will get a more accurate idea of their performance, and they will be assured that users of the transcript will also have this knowledge.” (Bar et al. 2009, p. 93–94 [italics mine]).
Additional reasons for sidestepping ethics codes in moral evaluation is discussed in Schwartz (2000).
Please keep in mind that John does not have to share the moral perspective from which I am performing this analysis. He can have moral beliefs based on, say, some deontological perspective, while Roberts and I execute our analyses from within a utilitarian framework. Or John might be miscalculating and consequently might have false beliefs about the moral properties of his potential actions.
A more precise term in discussions of rule-based utilitarian approaches might be the notion of “conformance utility” developed in Feldman (1978).
For the deontological-consequentialist distinction in Ethics, see https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/. Fidelity, roughly the duty to keep one’s promises, is one of the five fundamental moral duties according to Ross (1930).
Feldman (1978) concisely discusses a number of these putative shortcomings.
Is it possible that “does an act hurtful to others” is about action types rather than tokens? Since this is really not the main point of my essay, I will leave the answer to Mill scholars.
I emphasize that this does not make me a moral subjectivist. One can consistently assert that what one considers to be morally relevant is determined by one’s moral theory while maintaining that only one of these theories is correct whether we know which one, or not.
What I say here is about metaphysical constitution: what is constitutive of the fact that a given action instantiates a moral property like being obligatory in a specific situation.
I say only “quite probable” because it is possible that Roberts will embrace the additional morally relevant facts in my description as morally relevant factors he missed. Alternatively I might discover, after all, that what I thought was morally relevant is not morally relevant. Given these epistemic possibilities, it could be that we are utilizing the same moral theory after all.
Please keep in mind that what I call “my perspective or theory” need not be my theory. It is a theory which emulates certain aspects of Roberts approach (emphasis on doing harm) while departing from it with respect to the moral relevance of certain harms. I am not committed to this moral approach.
This objection is based on the comments of an anonymous referee.
I do wonder what the results of research focusing on the latter question would have been 150 years ago.
Kauppinen (2014) is an interesting discussion of experimental philosophy.
Chowning and Campbel (2009) has a concise definition of entitlement and proposes a metric for measuring it.
Casanova et al. (1797, pp. 93–95) presents pertinent evidence as a participant-observer.
References
Abbott, W. M. (2008). The politics of grade inflation: a case study. Change, 40(1), 32–37.
Armstrong, D. M. (1978). Universals and scientific realism. Reidel Publishing Company.
Bar, T., Kadiyali, V., & Zussman, A. (2009). Grade information and grade inflation: The Cornell experiment. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 23(3), 93–108.
Betts, J. R., & Grogger, J. (2003). The impact of grading standards on student achievement, educational attainment, and entry-level earnings. Economics of Education Review, 22, 343–352.
Bonnesrøning, H. (2004). Do the teachers’ grading practices affect student achievement? Education Economics, 12(2), 151–167.
Brown, C. L., & Kosovich, S. M. (2015). The impact of professor reputation and section attributes on student course selection. Research in Higher Education, 56(5), 496–509. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11162-014-9356-5
Brown, D. G. (1978). Mill on harm to others’ interests. Political Studies, 26(3), 395–399.
Carter, M. J., & Lara, P. Y. (2016). Grade inflation in higher education: Is the end in sight? Academic Questions, 29(3), 346–353.
Casanova, Giacomo, Chevalier de Sengault. (1797). Histoire de Ma Vie. English translation as History of my Life by Willard R. Trask (1966). New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.
Chowning, K., & Campbell, N. J. (2009). Development and validation of a measure of academic entitlement: Individual differences in students’ externalized responsibility and entitled expectations. Journal of Educational Psychology, 101(4).
Crumbley, D. L., Flinn, R. E., & Reichelt, K. J. (2010). What is ethical about grade inflation and coursework deflation? Journal of Academic Ethics, 8, 187–197.
De Haan, J. (2001). The definition of moral dilemmas: A logical problem. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 4, 267–284.
Emmons, D. C. (1967). Moral relevance. Ethics, 77(3), 224–228.
Fassin, Y. (2008). The stakeholder model refined. Journal of Business Ethics, 84, 113–135.
Feldman, F. (1978). Introductory ethics. Prentice-Hall.
Franz, W. I. (2016). Grade inflation under the threat of students’ nuisance: Theory and evidence. Economics of Education Review, 29(3), 411–422.
Frazier, R. L. (1995). Moral relevance and ceteris paribus principles. Ratio, 8, 113–125.
Grant, D., & Green, W. B. (2013). Grades as incentives. Empirical Economics, 44, 1563–1592.
Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge University Press.
Hindriks, F. (2014). How autonomous are collective agents? Corporate rights and normative individualism. Erkenntnis, 79, 1565–1585.
Kauppinen, A. (2014). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. In Joshua Knobe, and Shaun Nichols (Eds), Experimental philosophy: Volume2. pp. 3–30 (New York).
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press.
Kutz, C. (2000): Complicity: Ethics and law for a collective age (Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Law). Cambridge University Press.
Lawson, B. (2013). Individual complicity in collective wrongdoing. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16, 227–243.
Mill, J. S. (1859). On liberty. Parker and Son: John W.
Moore, D., Swift, S., Sharek, Z., & Gino, F. (2010). Correspondence bias in performance evaluation: Why grade inflation works. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin, 36, 843–852.
Norcross, A. (1995). Should utilitarianism accommodate moral dilemmas? Philosophical Studies, 79(1), 59–83.
Popov, S. V., & Bernhardt, D. (2013). University competition, grading standards, and grade inflation. Economic Inquiry, 51(3), 1764–1778.
Rescher, N. (2015). Excellence examined. Mind & Society, 14, 85–97.
Roberts, R. C. (2016). Are some of the things faculty do to maximize their student evaluation of teachers scores unethical? Journal of Academic Ethics, 14, 133–148.
Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schwartz, M. (2000). Why ethical codes constitute an unconscionable regression. Journal of Business Ethics, 23(2), 173–184.
Sharon, T., & Kingsley, P. (2012). Grade inflation, what students value, and the necessity of suffering. Proceedings of the 17th ACM Annual Conference on Innovation and Technology in Computer Science Education, (ITiCSE '12), 116–121. https://doi.org/10.1145/2325296.2325327
Shaughnessy, M. F., Moore, J., & Eisenman, R. (2004). An empirical examination of college students requesting a reduction in grades: with implications for grade inflation, university administration values, and evaluation of faculty. Journal of Evolutionary Psychology, 25(3–4), 212+.
Singleton-Jackson, J. A., Jackson, D. L., & Reinhardt, J. (2010). Students as consumers of knowledge: Are they buying what we’re selling? Innovative Higher Education, 35, 343–358.
Stroebe, W. (2020). Student evaluations of teaching encourages poor teaching and contributes to grade inflation: A theoretical and empirical analysis. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 42(4), 276–294. https://doi.org/10.1080/01973533.2020.1756817
Swift, S. A., Moore, D. A., Sharek, Z. S., & Gino, F. (2013). Inflated applicants: Attribution errors in performance evaluation by professionals. PLoS ONE 8(7), e69258. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0069258
Tamburrini, C. (2011). What’s wrong with J.S. Mill’s Harm-to-Others-Principle? Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 38(1), 1–26. https://doi.org/10.1080/00948705.2011.9714546
Tukibayeva, M. (2017). The relationships between faculty grading orientations, faculty preferences for types of learning assessment, and grades (Order No. 10685043). Available from ProQuest Dissertations & Theses Global. (2013173449). Retrieved from http://search.proquest.com.jproxy.lib.ecu.edu/docview/2013173449?accountid=10639
Veebel, V., Hurt, U., & Markus, R. (2013). Supranational institutions as central stakeholders during eurozone debt crisis in 2008–2012. Journal of Governance and Regulation, 202(4), 74–84.
White, K., & Heitzler, E. (2018). Effect of increased evaluation objectivity on grade inflation. Nurse Educator, 43(2), 73–77. https://doi.org/10.1097/NNE.0000000000000420
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Conflict of Interest
The author declares that they have no conflict of interest.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Yalçın, Ü.D. Analyzing Grade Inflators: Some Metaethical Issues. J Acad Ethics (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10805-023-09473-9
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10805-023-09473-9