Skip to main content
Log in

Rescuing Liberalism from Silencing

  • Published:
Journal of Academic Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I criticize two recent and influential arguments for no-platforming advanced by Robert Simpson and Amia Srinivasan and by Neil Levy, respectively. What both arguments have in common is their attempt to reconcile no-platforming with liberal values. For Simpson and Srinivasan, no-platforming does not contradict liberalism if grounded on the distinction between norms of free speech and norms of academic freedom; for Levy, those who defend the practice need not be accused of promoting paternalism. I argue that neither view succeeds: these authors’ views are in strong tension with core tenets of liberalism. I proceed as follows: after introducing some basic liberal principles, I explain Simpson and Srinivasan’s argument in more detail and argue that it is too strong for some their stated purposes; then I proceed to show that both Simpson and Srinivasan and Levy’s arguments would justify extremely closed universities; finally, after arguing that Levy’s stance does not circumvent paternalism, I present some evidence that no-platforming would be captured by censors and probably threaten the very academic freedom that the authors want to protect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A left-liberal such as Nagel, for instance, writes that the “liberal ideal is not content with the legal protection of free speech for fascists but also includes a social environment in which fascists can keep their counsel if they choose” (2002, p 22). We can probably say the same of libertarians such as Robert Nozick, who would accommodate freedom of speech within his theory of individual rights. But the strength of John Rawls’ commitment to free speech is a separate case. It is well known that in his Theory of Justice he includes the right to free speech in his First Principle of Justice. What not many people know is that in 1991 the philosopher himself was involved in a free speech controversy. In an interview for a Harvard Crimson issue, he was asked about the case of a student who had hanged a confederate flag in a dormitory window. Rawls acknowledges that the idea transmitted by the flag is utterly unjustified, but he also suggests that he would not sanction the student. The interview can be read at http://www.hcs.harvard.edu/~hrp/issues/1991/Rawls.pdf. Access on June 08, 2020.

  2. See Kramer (2000) for a contemporary articulation of this view.

  3. Of course, if I’m not a Harvard student, I can’t invite people to give a talk there. Nor am I saying that a university is never allowed to withdraw an invitation or is always obliged to invite all points of view. Rejecting no-platforming is consistent with all this.

  4. Although CLU is a fictional institution, its values are not. The Woodward Report, issued by Yale University in 1975, can be understood as a strong commitment to CLU’s central values. Drawing on the experience of several instances of disinvitations and deplatforming attempts, the signatories agreed on many proposals about speech policies. Here are some examples: “It is desirable that individuals and groups register in a wide-open and robust fashion their opposition to the views of a speaker with whom they disagree or whom they find offensive. When such a speaker has been invited to the campus by one group, other groups may seek to dissuade the inviters from proceeding. But it is a punishable offense against the principles of the University for the objectors to coerce others physically or to threaten violence” (p. 30); “Nor does the content of the speech, even parts deemed defamatory or insulting, entitle any member of the audience to engage in disruption” (p. 31); “The banning or obstruction of lawful speech can never be justified on such grounds as that the speech or the speaker is deemed irresponsible, offensive, un scholarly, or untrue” (p. 30); and “The University and its schools should retain an open and flexible system of registering campus groups, arranging for the reservation of rooms, and permitting groups freely to invite speakers” (p. 32). The document can be found at https://www.yale.edu/sites/default/files/files/freedom1975.pdf. Access on august 06, 2020.

  5. Second-order evidence about universities can be found on the Internet too. Greg Lukianoff’s FIRE makes an annual list of what it sees as the worst colleges for free speech; Jonathan Haidt’s Heterodox Academy displays a lot of material on this issue (one of the reasons stated by this advocacy group for awarding The University of Chicago’s commitment to free speech is its ban on no-platforming); and Quillette, an online magazine founded by Australian journalist Claire Lehmann, is very attentive to campus issues. A more detailed discussion, connecting the debate to recent cultural developments, can be found in Campbell and Manning (2018).

  6. Thus, the example seems to match Levy’s more precise definition of epistemic paternalism: “the management of an agent’s epistemic environment without (or regardless of) her consent, in order to promote her epistemic welfare” (2019, p. 5).

  7. Notice that I have no reason to complain if a TV channel decides to remove disreputable people from its shows. Since TV channels are autonomous, they can hire or fire whoever they want. Most instances of no-platforming, however, involve interference similar to that of the NGO.

  8. When discussing Levy’s thesis, I assumed that being given a platform automatically generates credibility for the sake of simplicity. My objections against it do not depend on the denial of this effect.

  9. Some of these ideas are defended by academics themselves. The work of the philosopher Stephen Kershnar is a case in point.

  10. More details on Tuvel’s case can be read at https://nymag.com/intelligencer/2017/05/transracialism-article-controversy.html. Access on June 08, 2020.

  11. Notice that if the absence of controversies justified no-platforming, it would be hard to see how one could challenge wrong consensuses previously established. How would we defend a lecture by Galileo if all other relevant experts were geocentrists?

  12. Langbert (2018) provides data on the political imbalance at American universities. Needless to say, the same arguments could be soundly offered if the imbalance favored right-wing views.

References

  • Brennan, J. Various Thoughts on Campus Free Speech [Blog post]. Bleeding Heart Libertarians, March 7, 2017. Available in <http://bleedingheartlibertarians.com/2017/03/various-thoughts-campus-free-speech/>. Access on July 07, 2020.

  • Campbell, B., & Manning, J. (2018). The rise of victimhood culture. Cham: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duarte, J., Jarret, L., Crawford, T., Stern, C., Haidt, J., Jussin, L., & Tetlock, P. E. (2015). Political diversity will improve social psychological science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 38, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. “Paternalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/paternalism/>. Access on June 08, 2020.

  • Dworkin, R. (1996). Freedom's law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslan, N. (2016). Concept creep: Psychology’s expanding concepts of harm and pathology. Psychological Inquiry, 27, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, M., Haynor, A., & Kickham, K. (2018). Sociology’s sacred victims and the politics of knowledge: Moral foundations theory and disciplinary controversies. The American Sociologist, 49, 459–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inbar, Y., & Lammers, J. (2012). Political diversity in social and personality psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 496–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. H. (2000) “Rights Without Trimmings.” In A Debate Over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

  • Langbert, M. (2018). Homogenous: The political affiliations of elite Liberal arts college faculty. Academic Questions, 31, 186–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2019) “No-Platforming and Higher-Order Evidence, or Anti-Anti-No-Platforming.” The Journal of the American Philosophical Association, p. 1–16.

  • Lukianoff, G., & Haidt, J. (2018). The coddling of the American mind. New York: Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (2015). How ideology has hindered sociological insight. The American Sociologist, 47, 115–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (2008). On Liberty and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mutz, D. (2006). Hearing the other side: Deliberative versus participatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2002). Concealment and exposure and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Post, R. (2013) Democracy, expertise, Academic Freedom. A First Amendment Jurisprudence for the Modern State. New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, R., & Srinivasan, A. (2018). No platforming. In J. Lackey (Ed.), Academic freedom (pp. 186–209). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuvel, R. (2017) “In Defense of Tranracialism.” Hypatia, vol. 32/2, p. 263–278.

  • Wall, S. (2015). Introduction. In S. Wall (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to liberalism (pp. 1–18). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

thank Lucas Miotto, Hélio Carneiro, Claiton Costa, Bruna Frascolla, and Eduardo César for helpful discussions on earlier drafts of this paper. I also thank the anonymous referees for their invaluable suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aluizio Couto.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Couto, A. Rescuing Liberalism from Silencing. J Acad Ethics 19, 465–481 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10805-020-09383-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10805-020-09383-0

Keywords

Navigation