1 Introduction

Bringing about good outcomes typically makes agents worthy of praise, just as bringing about bad outcomes typically makes agents worthy of blame.Footnote 1 Blameworthy agents are obliged to apologize and make amends for the bad outcomes that they bring about. Agents that fulfil their obligations in this regard may become worthy of forgiveness and perhaps even reconciliation with those negatively affected by their actions. The issue whether these patterns of evaluation are as applicable to collectives as they are to individuals is a controversial one. Part of the controversy stems from doubts about the existence of collective agents. While complex synergies may arise between the intentions and actions of individual group members, perhaps collectives as such cannot form intentions and react appropriately to being praised or blamed. That collectives should be so capable is arguably a requirement for them to be agents and thus eligible for assignments of moral responsibility in the first place.Footnote 2

The practice of holding collectives responsible by blaming and praising them is also made controversial by its perceived risk of unfairly affecting individual group members. While the unfairness objection is rarely articulated very clearly in the philosophical literature, expressions of its underlying worries are manifold.Footnote 3 One such worry is that holding collectives morally responsible by blaming them harms their individual group members. This could be considered very unfair, specifically in cases where the bad outcomes produced by the collectives are of a sort to lie beyond the intentional control of any of their individual group members. If there are reasons to suspect that the practice of collective responsibility will often end up being unfair in this way, then this might recommend a rejection of the practice altogether—or so the argument goes.

The following paper distinguishes between different versions of the unfairness objection and argues that the worries that crop up for the practice of collective responsibility will also be relevant to the practice of individual responsibility. It is therefore unclear what reasons there are to think that there is something uniquely morally problematic about the former practice but not the latter. To make the point, a distinction is also drawn between two kinds of fittingness conditions: On the one hand, there are conditions that determine whether the attitudes of blame and praise are fitting in respect of a given target; On the other hand, there are conditions that determine whether and by what means it is fitting to express attitudes. The distinction is generalized and is shown, along with several other theoretical considerations, to undermine the different versions of the unfairness objection.

2 Holding and Expressing Attitudes in Individual Cases

Individuals that are responsible for good outcomes are typically praiseworthy (it may be fitting to praise them) for those outcomes and individuals that are responsible for bad outcomes are typically blameworthy (it may be fitting to blame them) for those outcomes.Footnote 4 To hold individuals responsible for good outcomes is to praise them for those outcomes and to hold individuals responsible for bad outcomes is to blame them for those outcomes. The conditions under which individuals are responsible are often entwined with the conditions under which it is fitting to hold them responsible. Nevertheless, it is possible to hold individuals responsible for outcomes without overt expressions of praise or blame, as attitudes that are held need not be faithfully expressed.Footnote 5 The conditions under which it is fitting to hold individuals responsible can therefore be distinguished from the conditions that determine whether and by what means expressions of attitudes are fitting.

The distinction between the different conditions that pertain to attitudes and their expression is often alluded to in the philosophical literature. Within the context of discussions about moral responsibility, it is usually referred to in terms of public and private blame. Sarah Gokhale is among the philosophers to develop the distinction and to emphasize one of the ideas referred to in what follows, namely that there tend to be higher stakes associated with public blame than there are with its private counterpart.Footnote 6 It should also be noted that while the present discussion is explicitly couched in terms of fittingness, Gokhale and other philosophers writing about public and private blame often invoke other normative notions. It should therefore be noted that the arguments offered here work just as well when formulated in terms of the fittingness of attitudes and, say, the rightness, propriety, or correctness of their expression.

The important point to notice is that there might well be situations where an individual is responsible for a good outcome (making the individual a fitting target of praise for those outcomes) even though it is unfitting to express praise toward the individual. Similarly, there may be situations where an individual is responsible for bad outcomes (making the individual fitting targets of blame for those outcomes) even though it would be unfitting to express blame toward the individual. Such cases may be rare, but they are not difficult to imagine. Suppose Kate thinks too highly of herself and is at risk of becoming a narcissist were she to become the knowing recipient of any more praise. It can be imagined that if Kate becomes a narcissist, then this will significantly decrease her chances of producing good outcomes in the future. Kate might therefore be the fitting target of praise for the good outcomes that she produces, even though overt expressions of praise toward her are ultimately unfitting.Footnote 7

The case just mentioned illustrates that overt praise of a praiseworthy individual can benefit that individual in ways that she does not deserve and that leads to bad outcomes. While such considerations may affect the conditions that determine whether and by what means expressions of attitudes are fitting, they need not affect the conditions that determine whether an individual like Kate is a fitting target of praise. This can also be illustrated by less exotic examples, whereby the overt praise of a praiseworthy individual benefits the friends and family of that individual in undeserved ways. When Kate is overtly praised by a large group of people for the good outcomes she produces, her friends and family may start to enjoy social benefits which they have not earned or of which they have not made themselves deserving. If the benefits are significant, this may also have relevance for the issue whether and by what means expressions of praise will be fitting.

Consider next Laura who is suffering from severe depression risks harming herself were she to become a knowing recipient of any more blame. It can be imagined that the bad outcomes produced by Laura are minor ones and of a sort to affect her more than anyone else. This seems like a case where Laura is the fitting target of blame for the bad outcomes that she produces even though overt expressions of blame toward her are ultimately unfitting. Indeed, it seems plausible to go a step further and suggest that vociferous praise for the good outcomes produced by Laura is fitting even though this does not quite match the level of praise that she is earned by the value of the outcomes themselves. The reason is that this would represent a positive reinforcement that may facilitate Laura’s recovery from severe depression and thereby decrease the risk that she continues to produce bad outcomes.Footnote 8

The case just described shows that the overt blame of a blameworthy individual can harm that individual. Again, while this consideration may affect the conditions that determine whether and by what means expressions of negative attitudes are fitting, they do not affect the conditions that determine whether Laura is a fitting target of blame. Just as before, this can also be illustrated by less exotic examples, whereby the overt blame of a blameworthy individual instead harms the friends and family of that individual. When Laura is overtly blamed by a large group of people for the bad outcomes that she produces, her friends and family may be forced to endure social harms. If the harms in question are significant, then this may have relevance for the issue whether and by what means expressions of blame are fitting.

The fitting targets of blame are often the fitting targets of punishment, just as the fitting targets of praise are often the fitting targets of reward. Imprisoning a parent for a crime may have adverse effects on her closest family. In addition to being deprived of support and companionship, their partner may face the emotional and economic hardships that are associated with becoming a single parent. As a result, their children could suffer abandonment and shame, eventually contributing to depression and anger later in life. While considerations regarding these kinds of destabilizing effects on the family can motivate a mitigation of the punishment by courts, this would not necessarily be because imprisonment as such is thought to be unfitting, or that the courts would regard them as punitive for the family.Footnote 9

Giving a prestigious award to a political activist in an authoritarian nation for their civil right struggles could have adverse effects for the political activist and her friends. The increased attention resulting from her receiving the reward may exacerbate the harsh treatment imposed by the state, who would be incentivized to turn the political activist and their friends into cautionary tales.Footnote 10 While considerations of this kind may play a part in a decision to withhold any awards until the situation improves, this would not necessarily imply that the awards themselves are unfitting. Even if steps are taken to avoid the morally innocent from being adversely affected, strictly speaking, adverse effects do not undermine the fittingness of the rewards themselves. Facts about the practical effects of giving a reward to a political activist is not of the kind to determine whether the reward as such is fitting.

The analogies involving sanctions and rewards are not perfect since they do not present a close corollary to the distinction between expressing attitudes and merely holding them. Nevertheless, they do help illustrate the additional point that considerations regarding the practical effects of a response, which may reasonably affect a decision about whether and by what means it should be carried out, need not affect the fittingness of the response as such. The examples involving attitudes and their expression are a special case, for the fittingness of holding attitudes such as praise or blame need not be affected by global considerations concerning the practical value of their expression. Inasmuch as such considerations of unfairness have weight, it is at least not typically to be found in a decision whether to praise or blame, but in a decision whether and by what means to express these attitudes.Footnote 11 There will be more on this, but before that we will revisit the unfairness objection.

3 Cashing Out the Unfairness Objection

It seems that the unfairness objection to the practice of collective responsibility can be cashed out in a multitude of ways depending on how collectives are thought and spoken about. Suppose Annie quits her office job because of the hostile work environment created by her male colleagues. When she expresses blame toward the men at her office for making her quit, she might have in mind each and every man at the office. This means that her collective talk is used as a shorthand allowing Annie to express blame toward many individuals without needing to mention every one of them. This aggregate way of treating individuals appears commonplace and so it is worth considering how it might be relevant to assessments of the unfairness objection. In fact, the most obvious worry in this context is very similar to the worries that were mentioned in the previous section, about the collateral damage that might result from assignments of moral responsibility specifically to individuals.

The lesson is that when talk of responsible collectives is used as a shorthand for talk of responsible individuals, care needs to be taken to mitigate the fact that some individuals are blamed, praised, sanctioned, or rewarded (or otherwise benefited or harmed) for outcomes for which they are not responsible. It is conceivable that if Annie were to clarify what individuals she has in mind, she might admit that she does not blame each and every man at her office. While the number of responsible men may still seem large enough to warrant the shorthand, a lack of contextual clues can make it difficult to infer whom Annie has in mind. As a result, her male colleagues might be unsure whether they are among the wrongdoers, just as the rest of us are unclear about where to direct our blame. If the practice of collective responsibility always worked like this, then it is easy to see how it might lead to unfair effects.

Indeed, part of the reason why people are often uncomfortable with the practice of collective responsibility could be that it is often talked about specifically as the unjust practice of blaming or punishing innocents for the behaviour of others. A classic example is the authoritarian practice of kin punishment, whereby individuals are punished for the deeds of a family member. Another classic example is the teacher’s practice of punishing children for the behaviour of their classmates. Note, though, that while cases such as these may often be described as cases of collective responsibility (or perhaps more commonly, collective punishment), they could just as well be described as misuses of the practice of individual responsibility.Footnote 12 After all, they essentially involve holding one or many persons individually responsible for outcomes for which they are not ultimately responsible.

This understanding of collective responsibility is reflected in the philosophical literature as well. When H. D. Lewis expresses his unfairness worry about the practice of collective responsibility, it seems clear that he has in mind the practice of blaming individuals for the outcomes produced by other individuals. He insists that “we cannot answer for another or share each other’s guilt (or merit), for that would imply that we could become directly worse (or better) persons morally by what others elect to do—and that seems plainly preposterous”.Footnote 13 What Lewis objects to, in other words, is the idea that an individual could produce an outcome and share responsibility for it with another individual who did not produce that outcome. While this is right as far as it goes, it seems fair to suggest that it neglects senses of collective responsibility that do not require shared guilt (or merit).Footnote 14

The idea is that rather than using her collective talk as a sort of shorthand for expressing blame toward one or many individuals, Annie might be targeting her blame toward a genuinely collective entity, like a collection of agents or even a collective agent.Footnote 15 The distinction between the two is rooted in the intuition that there are differences between groups comprised of independently acting agents and integrated collectives that form intentions in unison, perhaps in accordance with established decision procedures.Footnote 16 Annie might be forced to quit her job because each and every man at her office happens to be rude and lacking in empathy. Such a case, where a regretful outcome is realized by independently acting men, is different from a case where the men are parts of an integrated community, characterized by goals and values that lead to harsher conditions for other office workers.

Attempts have been made to account for collective agency, but no such account enjoys wide acceptance within the literature. While the existence of mere collections of agents is far less controversial, their lack of joint agency is often taken to suggest that they are the unfitting targets of responsibility assignments.Footnote 17 Note that if mere collections of agents cannot be morally responsible, then the main objection to the practice of holding them responsible is not that doing so leads to unfair effects for individuals, but that the practice as such is misguided. On the other hand, if mere collections of agents can be the fitting targets of praise and blame, then the practice of holding such collections responsible is subject to many of the same unfairness worries as the practice of assigning moral responsibility to collective agents. The following discussion therefore takes on a general perspective that is meant to apply regardless of whether the practice of collective responsibility involves mere collections of agents or collective agents.

The point emphasized in what follows is that both the practice of collective responsibility and the practice of individual responsibility may result in collateral damage and that both are susceptible to misuses that mirror the collective punishment cases described earlier. It should be noted that some of the philosophers that present an unfairness objection to the practice of collective responsibility would agree. Sverdlik is among them, for he is careful to point out that it would be unfair, “whether we are considering a result produced by more than one person’s action or by a single person, to blame a person for a result that he or she did not intend to produce” (emphasis added).Footnote 18 This remark displays an awareness and appreciation of the fact that both the practice of collective responsibility and the practice of individual responsibility involve the potential of unfair effects. This fact remains relevant regardless of whether the practice involves mere collections of agents or collective agents.

The question, then, is whether holding collective entities responsible is more likely to result in unfair effects than the practice of holding individuals morally responsible. Making progress on the issue requires looking closer at what it means to hold collectives morally responsible in the first place, as well as the commitments that might be involved in blaming, praising, sanctioning, and rewarding them. Some reasons have already been given for believing that the practice of collective responsibility need not be more problematic than the practice of individual responsibility, but it is worth pausing on some of those reasons for a bit longer. This will help rule out potential sources of unfairness and further highlight the parallels between the two practices.Footnote 19 The distinction between collective agents and mere collections of agents will be reconsidered later, when the question is asked whether there might be more specific formulations of the unfairness objection that remain to be explored.

4 Holding and Expressing Attitudes in Collective Cases

Philosophers worrying about the practice of collective responsibility are often focused on the issuing of sanctions. For example, when Björn Petersson and Govert den Hartogh express their respective unfairness worries, both bring up cases where individual group members are not just blamed but punished for outcomes that are produced by the their respective collectives.Footnote 20 Petersson warns us that “collective sanctions strike individual members” and that we therefore need to demarcate collective agents so that the only individuals that end up struck are those “that justifiably can be blamed for what the group has done”.Footnote 21 Den Hartogh similarly states that when groups are sanctioned “some individuals will in the end have to take on the burdens of that punishment” and that this is unfair “if they have done nothing for which they personally deserve to be blamed, or at least to be blamed to that extent”.Footnote 22

The previous section distinguished individualistic readings of collective talk from the more robustly collective interpretations discussed here, but not enough was said about what the practice of collective responsibility involves. Part of the practice is assumed to involve the adoption of blame and praise, but what remains to be explored is the connection between the fittingness of such attitudes and the fittingness of issuing sanctions and rewards. Petersson and den Hartogh seem to assume that the practice of issuing sanctions is central to the practice of collective responsibility and this grounds some of their unfairness worries. Roughly, the worry is that individual group members cannot be left alone while the collective entities that they constitute are fined, imprisoned, or made to pick up roadside garbage. Many punishments that are directed toward collective agents will strike individual group members as well.Footnote 23

The argument might be made that while issuing sanctions and rewards is central to practices of legal responsibility, it has little to do with practices of moral responsibility, but this would go too far. Firstly, it seems very plausible to suggest that the factors that make things the fitting targets of attitudes often contribute to making them the fitting targets of sanctions and rewards as well. Secondly, some of the sanctions and rewards that are involved in practices of moral responsibility may not be of the legal but of the social variety (consider cases where agents become the fitting target of exclusion from certain social arrangements).Footnote 24 What sanctions and rewards are called for by instances of collective responsibility and whether these differ from those that are called for by instances of individual responsibility is an open question that deserves more attention, but it has to be set aside for now.

Notice that sanctions and rewards seem to be characterized by a certain kind of goal-directedness. This is reflected in the intuitive distinction between being punished or rewarded, on the one hand, and being affected by the punishments or rewards bestowed on someone else, on the other.Footnote 25 When the courts punish a parent for a crime, their aim is to inflict some harm upon the parent that is constitutive of the punishment. While the punishment is also likely to have negative effects on the family of the accused, it is not the aim of the justice system to bestow any harm upon them and so they are not punished. This suggests that what is done to collectives need not be done to their individual group members. T. H. Smith makes the very same point and he thinks it applies just as much to attitudes as it does to sanctions and rewards:

Now, an act or attitude can be targeted at a plurality without it, any part or portion of it, or anything of the same kind as it, being targeted at any one of them: an actor who fears his audience targets his fear at them, but may not target it, or any part or portion of it, or any act or attitude of the same kind as it, at any one of his audience. Likewise, an award can be given to a plurality without it, or any part or portion of it, or anything of the same kind as it, being given to any one of them. Sometimes, perhaps, a single award goes to each of a plurality, as when a tie occurs. But when the achievement recognized has been done in collaboration (one thinks of Oscars and Nobel prizes), an award will go to a plurality, none of whom receive it, any part or portion of it, or anything of the same kind as it.Footnote 26

It seems right to suggest that collective entities can be held responsible without their individual group members necessarily becoming praised or blamed. As Smith indicates, the claim can be supported by making comparisons with the attitudes that are called for by values other than blameworthiness and praiseworthiness. A lovable person can be fittingly loved without all her constituent parts or characteristic features necessarily becoming loved, just as an admirable artwork can be fittingly admired without all its brushstrokes necessarily becoming admired, just as a preferable world can be fittingly preferred to another possible world without every state in the former necessarily becoming preferred to every state of the latter. It may be that when some attitudes are directed toward an object, some of the properties or constituent parts of the object will be featured in the intentional contents of the attitudes. Nevertheless, as Noah Lemos rightly points out, this does not mean that each such property or part is as much of a target of the attitudes as the object that bears them.Footnote 27

The properties or constituent parts of an object could be featured in the intentional contents of attitudes indirectly, not as the intended targets of the attitudes in question, but as the things that characterize and help identify their intended targets.Footnote 28 The objection might be made that attitudes cannot be directed toward an object without the attitudes thereby being directed toward some of its parts, but it is unclear what reasons there are for thinking that this is true. It is not shown to be true by the mere fact that fitting attitudes are always directed toward objects for some of their constituent parts or characteristic features.Footnote 29 A consideration can make certain attitudes fitting without thereby becoming a fitting target of the same kinds of attitudes.

What this shows is that there are wider axiological discussions to be had about the nature of attitudes and whether favouring and disfavouring objects requires the favouring and disfavouring of their respective parts or properties.Footnote 30 From this wider perspective, it seems intuitive to suggest that favouring and disfavouring objects does not necessarily require the favouring and disfavouring of their respective parts or properties. The point is that if those general intuitions have any validity, then they apply here too, and lend support to the view that holding collective entities responsible does not necessarily require holding individuals responsible. Proponents of the unfairness objection might acknowledge this point and maintain that though the practice of collective responsibility does not generally require the blame and praise of individual group members, there are instances where it does.

In other words, the idea might be that there are specific situations, perhaps involving certain types of collectives and outcomes, where the practice of collective responsibility does involve the unfair blame and praise of individual group members. For example, perhaps there are salient differences between mere collections of agents and collective agents such that the practice of holding one responsible for an outcome tends to produce more unfair effects than the other. This means that the unfairness objection is weaker than it might first appear, involving no general claim about the connection between the practice of collective responsibility and the unfair blame or praise of individual group members. Of course, there is then a challenge on part of its proponents to explain what the problematic instances look like (i.e. what it is about the relevant types of collectives and outcomes that leads to a disruption in the goal-directedness of actions and the intentional structure of attitudes), just as they need to show that they involve cases where the practice of collective responsibility truly does end up being unfair.

For now, it seems safe to suggest that the unfairness objection is on somewhat shaky ground if it is based on the general claim that holding collectives responsible for outcomes necessarily requires holding potentially innocent individuals responsible as well.Footnote 31 The points made above about the goal-directedness of actions, as well as the discernment and intentional structure of attitudes, indicate that this is not a guarantee. Nevertheless, while holding collectives responsible for outcomes does not necessarily require holding individuals responsible for those outcomes, individuals could nonetheless be affected in unfair ways by the practice of collective responsibility. Velasquez shares some of the worries of Petersson and den Hartogh and thinks that they apply both to the adoption of attitudes and the issuing of sanctions and rewards. He has this to say about the effects of holding collectives morally responsible:

But in fact it is not possible to impose blame or punishment upon an organizational structure without having that blame or punishment fall on the shoulders of the corporation’s members. It is the members who will feel all the effects and bear all the injuries if the corporation’s structures are “fined,” if its “public image” is “tarnished,” or if these structures are altered or perhaps even dissolved. These members are therefore being unjustly forced to bear the punishment for another entity’s moral responsibility (in addition to any punishment they may have to bear for their own moral responsibility for the act).Footnote 32

This is perhaps one of the clearest formulations of the unfairness objection in the philosophical literature and it does not say that holding collective agents morally responsible necessarily requires holding potentially innocent individuals morally responsible. Instead, what it says is that potentially innocent individuals will inevitably be affected by the practice of collective moral responsibility in other ways that are unfair. Even if there is something to this, it is once again unclear whether this makes the practice of collective responsibility different from its individual counterpart. We saw in an earlier section that there is a potential for unfair effects in cases of individual responsibility as well. The examples that were used to illustrate this point can be adapted to cases where collectives are held morally responsible for an outcome.

There may be conceivable situations where collectives are responsible for good outcomes (making them fitting targets of praise for those outcomes) even though it is unfitting to express praise toward them. Suppose a collective produces a good outcome that lies beyond the intentional control of its individual group members. Imagine too that if the collective as such becomes a target of overt praise, then some of its individual group members will suffer bad outcomes. These may well represent the kinds of situations where the collective as such is worthy of praise, even though overt expressions of blame toward the collective ends up being unfitting. Perhaps the example could be imagined in more detail, as a collective counterpart to the previously discussed example involving Kate. The collective group members think, intend, and act in such a way as to produce a collective action that leads to a good outcome. The collective may to that extent be praiseworthy, but because each member of the collective is as narcissistic as Kate is, the knowledge that they are parts of a praised collective might decrease their chances of thinking, intending, and acting in the right way again.

There may also be situations where collectives are responsible for bad outcomes (making them fitting targets of blame for those outcomes) even though it would be unfitting to express blame toward them. Suppose that a collective produces a bad outcome that lies beyond the intentional control of its individual group members and that those group members would suffer bad results if the collective as such became the target of overt blame. The bad outcomes suffered by the individual group members could even be worse than the bad outcome that they originally produced as a collective. This represents the kind of situation where the collective as such is worthy of blame, even though expressions of blame toward it ends up being unfitting. This example could be described as a collective counterpart to the one involving Laura. While each member acts in a blameless way, the collective action that results produces slightly worse outcomes for all of them. The collective may to that extent be blameworthy, but because each member of the collective is as emotionally fragile as Laura is, they risk harming themselves were they to become knowing parts of a blamed collective.

Local considerations affecting the conditions under which it is fitting to hold collective agents responsible ought not to be confused with wider considerations determining whether and by what means it is fitting to express praise or blame toward collective agents. A similar point can be made regarding actions directed at collectives, although such cases tend to become more sophisticated and difficult to get a firm grip on. For example, in the arena of international politics, governments often impose economic sanctions on nations that result in significant negative effects for their citizens. The effects of these sanctions may be so severe that they start to affect the extent to which the citizens can satisfy their basic needs. There is a sense in which the sanction may still be fitting in respect of the collective, but its unfair effects on individual citizens may be such as to recommend that it not be carried out.

The argument has just been made that holding collective agents responsible for an outcome does not necessarily require holding individuals responsible for that outcome. Furthermore, the argument has also been made that the unfair effects of the practice of collective responsibility do not necessarily undermine the fittingness of blaming or praising collectives. The examples of previous sections do not just help to illustrate the generality of these specific points, but also help to show that the considerations of unfairness that crop up for cases of collective responsibility are ubiquitous in individual cases. The overt blame of blameworthy individuals can produce harms for those individuals and their loved ones, just as the overt praise of praiseworthy individuals can lead to undeserved benefits for those individuals and their friends. The practice of individual responsibility and that of collective responsibility therefore appear to be on equal ground as far as considerations of unfairness go.

If the practice of collective responsibility is unfair, then, this is because of factors that make the practice of individual responsibility unfair as well. Indeed, most of the points that have been made in this paper can be generalized beyond the domain of moral responsibility altogether, as considerations of unfairness are likely to crop up for many cases where values other than blameworthiness and praiseworthiness call for the adoption of attitudes. The previously mentioned examples involving lovability and admirability suffice to show that this is true. That Laura is worthy of love does not guarantee that her friends are worthy of the benefits resulting from her becoming loved. That an artwork is worthy of admiration does not guarantee that its creator is worthy of the benefits resulting from it becoming admired. Given the ubiquity of these kinds of considerations, it seems unlikely that they should present any deep problem specifically for a practice of collective responsibility.

For all that has just been said, there is admittedly something intuitive about the suggestion that the practice of collective responsibility is somehow more sensitive to considerations of unfairness, even though the same considerations are evidently relevant to all cases where the presence of value calls for the adoption of attitudes. Perhaps this is because practices of moral responsibility—be they individual or collective—have a social dimension that is meant to be more pronounced than in many other such practices. For example, responding to the moral responsibility of a person by either blaming or praising them is in some sense associated with greater moral stakes than responding to the beauty of a person by adopting an attitude of aesthetic appreciation. Another remnant of the unfairness objection is therefore a challenge to account for what these stakes might be and precisely how they could affect the fittingness of holding and expressing attitudes such as blame and praise.

5 Concluding Remarks

The purpose of the paper was not to justify indifference in respect of the outcomes that might be produced by the practice of collective responsibility. We have seen that care needs to be taken in its application to make sure that its outcomes do not affect individuals too unfairly. Rather, the paper was meant to show that these considerations of unfairness are ubiquitous and relevant in both collective and individual cases. The result is that it is difficult to see how the unfairness objection could present a deep and serious problem specifically for the practice of collective responsibility. Blaming or praising collectives as such does not necessarily require the blame or praise of individual group members, nor does the punishment of collectives necessarily require the punishment of individual group members. Moreover, while the practice of collective responsibility can affect individual group members in ways that might be considered unfair, this makes it no different from the practice of blaming or praising individual agents. Whenever an individual is targeted by attitudes such as blame and praise, or punished for the outcomes that they have produced, there is the risk that this will affect other individuals as well. Proponents of the unfairness objection therefore need to state more clearly what the effects are that supposedly undermine the practice of collective responsibility and how they differ from the effects that might result from the adoption of fitting attitudes in other contexts.