Nyāya philosophers since Pakṣilasvāmin Vātsyāyana (4th or 5th century CE) have thought that liberation (apavarga or mokṣa) is one of the highest goods (niḥśreyasa) of human existence; it is the highest good that the science of the self (adhyātma-vidyā) promotes. Nyāya is a science of critical inquiry (āṇvīkṣikī). It assists the science of the self (or functions as a science of the self itself) in two ways. On the one hand, it yields an awareness of the truth (tattva-jñāna) about various epistemological tools, e.g., the means of knowing (pramāṇa), etc. The knowledge of these tools is necessary for inquiring into liberation and the means to achieve it. On the other hand, Nyāya supplies us with an awareness of the truth about the knowable entities (prameya), e.g, the self (ātman), the body (śarīra), etc. Discovering that truth liberates us.Footnote 1

Most Nyāya philosophers offer a purely negative characterisation of liberation. Liberation, for them, is the absolute cessation of pain (ātyantika-duḥkha-vimukti). That involves freedom from repeated birth (janman) and, therefore, all aspects of embodied existence.Footnote 2 This raises a problem. Since pleasure can only arise within a body, a liberated being couldn’t experience pleasure. However, ordinary agents like us are motivated by (at least) two kinds of desires: the desire to obtain pleasure and things that give rise to pleasure, and the desire to avoid pain and things that bring about pain. But then it’s not obvious whether we can, or should, be motivated to seek liberation at all.

In this essay, I will look at a solution to this problem, given by Vātsyāyana in his commentary Nyāya-bhāṣya (NB) on the Nyāya-sūtra (NS). Vātsyāyana’s solution depends on what I shall call the Pain Principle, i.e., the principle that we should treat all aspects of embodied existence as pain. That explains why we should act solely from the motive of avoiding pain, and therefore should seek liberation in order to free ourselves from all pain involved in embodied existence. On Vātsyāyana’s proposal, we should treat all aspects of our embodied existence as pain, not because they are literally pain, but rather because they are inextricably connected to pain. This expansive application of the label of pain (duḥkha-saṃjñā) is supposed to undermine our attachment to embodied existence. I will explain how this idea connects up with Vātsyāyana’s thesis that thinking about the world under certain labels (saṃjñā) or concepts—some of which may inaccurately represent the world—plays an important role in transforming us into agents who are capable of seeking liberation.Footnote 3

Here is the plan for this essay. I will begin by laying out Vātsyāyana’s negative conception of liberation. Then, I will say why he rejects an alternative positive view according to which liberation involves the manifestation of permanent pleasure. This raises a problem for Vātsyāyana, namely that ordinary agents like us cannot be rationally motivated to seek liberation. After posing the problem, I will sketch Vātsyāyana’s response to this problem, and show how it, as it stands, is inadequate. I will then argue that the response can succeed if we take Vātsyāyana to be relying on the Pain Principle. Finally, I will explain how this principle fits with Vātsyāyana’s more general theory that cultivating different labels (saṃjñā) or concepts with respect to ourselves and the world can play an important role in transforming our patterns of motivation.

What Is Liberation?

Arguably, the Nyāya conception of liberation originates from Book VIII of the Chāndogya Upaniṣad.Footnote 4 Here, we find Indra, the king of the gods, and Virocana, the king of the demons, trying to engage another god, Prajāpati, in a dialogue about the nature of the self. Indra and Virocana want to discover the self, “by discovering which one obtains all the worlds, and all one’s desires are fulfilled.” At first, Prajāpati misleads them, making them believe that the self is just the body. Virocana goes back to the demons with this belief, which, Prajāpati predicts, will lead to their downfall. But Indra quickly notices that there would be nothing satisfying about discovering the self if the self were just the living body. The living body cannot be completely free from decay and death. So, if one were to discover that the self is nothing more than a body that is subject to decay and death, one’s desires (including the desire to be free from decay and death) wouldn’t be satisfied. Therefore, he returns to Prajāpati. Prajāpati misleads him once again, first suggesting that the self is just the consciousness that remains active even in dreams, and then suggesting that it is the unconscious body that persists even when one is in a state of deep sleep. In each case, Indra notices a problem. First, the consciousness that remains active in dreams can never be completely free from suffering. So, once again, there would be nothing satisfying about discovering that that is the self. Second, the unconscious person is incapable of having conscious thoughts and experiences about herself or other things, and thus lacks one of the essential characteristics of the self. At last, Prajāpati reveals the truth about the self to Indra: “This body, Maghavan, is mortal; it is in the grip of death. So, it is the abode of this immortal and nonbodily self. One who has a body is in the grip of joy and sorrow, and there is no freedom from joy and sorrow for one who has a body. Joy and sorrow, however, do not affect one who has no body.”Footnote 5 Thus, in this Upaniṣadic picture, the connection between the self and hedonic states like pleasure and pain is merely contingent: when the self inhabits the body, it is subject to pleasure and pain, but, when it is disembodied, it is affected by neither. For Nyāya philosophers like Vātsyāyana, liberation is simply this disembodied state of the self where it is invulnerable to pain.

To understand the Nyāya account of liberation, let’s start with a story that is laid out in NS as well as in Vātsyāyana’s commentary on it. According to NS 1.1.17, a practical undertaking (pravṛtti) is any effort (ārambha) that gives rise to a mental, linguistic or physical action. Such practical undertakings are produced by defects (doṣa): namely, attachment (rāga), aversion (dveṣa) and delusion (moha). These motivate us towards both vicious (pāpa) and virtuous (puṇya) practical undertakings (NB 20.3-7 on NS 1.1.18).Footnote 6 In his commentary on NS 1.1.20, Vātsyāyana says that our experiences (saṃvedana) of pleasure and pain are the results of our past practical undertakings and the defects that underlie them (NB 21.3-7). This idea is based on a background belief in the karmic law, the principle that our practical undertakings, depending on whether they are virtuous or vicious, give rise to an appropriate result, i.e., an experience of pain or pleasure. When an agent acts virtuously, her practical undertaking produces in her a dispositional property, i.e., merit (dharma), which gives rise to a future experience of pleasure. When an agent acts viciously, her practical undertaking produces in her a different dispositional property, i.e., demerit (adharma), which gives rise to a future experience of pain. Since merit and demerit are the immediate effects of practical undertakings, they count as practical undertakings in a derivative sense (NB 7.6-7 on NS 1.1.2). Since our embodied existence is just a sequence of one practical undertaking after another, we cannot possibly experience all the pleasures and pains that we deserve to experience in one life. Thus, in order to obtain these results, we must be born with the body, the senses, and so on. In this way, merit and demerit bind us in the cycle of rebirth (saṃsāra) where we acquire a body over and over again (NB 20.10-15, 21.3-7 and 212.12-213.7 on NS 1.1.19-20 and 3.2.66).

Liberation consists in an irreversible escape from this cycle of rebirth. According to NS 1.1.21, “pain is that which has the defining characteristic of distress (bādhanā)” (bādhanālakṣaṇaṃ duḥkham). In his commentary, Vātsyāyana says:

Distress is synonymous with affliction (pīḍā) and sorrow (tāpa). Anything, which is present inextricably intertwined (anuviddha) and connected (anuṣakta) with it, is pain in virtue of being related to pain. This being, who perceives that everything is intertwined by pain and desires to avoid pain, becomes dejected (nirvidyate) with respect to this birth (janman). Having become dejected (nirviṇṇa), he becomes detached. Having become detached, he becomes free.Footnote 7

The argument of this passage depends on the premise that, when a person sees that this birth is inseparably connected to (an overwhelming amount of) pain, she will come to see all aspects of it as pain. But what is birth? In his commentary on NS 4.1.55, Vātsyāyana explains: “Since ‘birth’ means that which is born [rather than to the event of being born], it stands for the body, the senses, and awareness-events (buddhi)” (janma jāyate iti śarīrendriyabuddhayaḥ).Footnote 8 So, birth encompasses both physical and psychological aspects of our embodied existence. When an agent sees this birth as pain, she will lose all attachment towards these aspects of embodied existence, and will desire to be free from it. In NS 1.1.22, Gautama says, “Liberation is absolute freedom from that” (tad-atyanta-vimokṣo’pavargaḥ). Vātsyāyana expands on this.

The absolute freedom from that pain which is birth is liberation. Why? Because it involves relinquishing the birth that has been appropriated, and not appropriating another such birth. Those who are learned in matters of liberation know this limitless state to be liberation.Footnote 9

Thus, if liberation is just absolute freedom from birth, it is a permanent disembodied state of the self.Footnote 10

How can we attain this disembodied state? NS 1.1.2 sketches a story: “When suffering, embodied existence, practical undertakings [or, alternatively, immediate effects of practical undertakings, namely merit and demerit], defect, and false awareness cease one after another, due to the cessation of what immediately follows from them, there is liberation” (duḥkha-janma-pravṛtti-doṣa-mithyā-jñānānām uttarottarāpāye tad-anantarāpāyād apavargaḥ). Vātsyāyana unpacks the story as follows. Our false awareness about the world and ourselves gives rise to the three defects, on the basis of which we engage in virtuous or vicious practical undertakings. These practical undertakings, by producing merit and demerit, come to cause future births. Thus, false awareness indirectly gives rise to the cycle of rebirth. Therefore, by eliminating such false awareness, we can eliminate each link in this causal chain, thereby completely eliminating pain (NB 6.9-8.3).

The Permanent Pleasure View

Vātsyāyana contrasts his conception of liberation with another view. According to this latter view, the state of liberation involves the manifestation (abhivyakti) of permanent pleasure (nitya-sukha).Footnote 11 Call this the Permanent Pleasure View. But Vātsyāyana thinks that there is no good evidence that this view is true.

Some think: “In liberation, the permanent pleasure of the self is manifested (abhivyajyate) just like its extension (mahattva). In virtue of that manifested pleasure, the absolutely free being is pleased.” They face a problem (anupapatti) due to the absence of any means of knowing. There exists neither perception nor inference nor any scriptural statement (āgama), which could show that, in liberation, just like the extension (mahattva) of the self, the permanent pleasure of the self is manifested.Footnote 12

Why? The argument is this. Suppose there is a manifestation of permanent pleasure in the state of liberation. Presumably, this is an experience (saṃvedana) or awareness of that pleasure. Either that awareness is non-permanent, or permanent. But it can’t be either. So, the Permanent Pleasure View is false. The crucial premise of this argument is that the awareness of permanent pleasure can be neither permanent nor impermanent. Let’s motivate that premise in light of what Vātsyāyana says.

If that awareness is non-permanent insofar as it has a beginning, the defender of the Permanent Pleasure View would have to say what causes it.Footnote 13 To avoid this line of questioning, she might argue that the awareness of permanent pleasure is also permanent i.e., without a beginning or an end. That is problematic, since it implies that the pleasure should also be always manifested in an ordinary state of embodied existence. This has two implausible consequences.Footnote 14 First of all, this would make it difficult to explain the distinction between someone who has achieved liberation and someone who hasn’t. After all, both would experience permanent pleasure! If the distinguishing characteristic of the state of liberation is the manifestation of permanent pleasure, the presence of that defining characteristic in an ordinary embodied state implies that there is no difference between the two states. Second, even if an embodied being could experience such permanent pleasure, it would experience such pleasure at the same time as and together with other pleasures and pains that arise as a result of the merit and demerit left by her previous practical undertakings. But such simultaneity and co-presence aren’t apprehended in ordinary experience.Footnote 15

The defender of the Permanent Pleasure might attempt to avoid these consequences by arguing that the awareness of permanent pleasure is impermanent, i.e., has a beginning. If it has a beginning, then it must be produced by something. For Vātsyāyana, our experiences of ordinary pleasures are produced by an internal monitoring mechanism—the manas—which serves as a faculty of introspective attention and makes us aware of our own hedonic states when it is conjoined to the self (NB 11.15-21 on NS 1.1.4). When the self possesses pleasure, the conjunction (saṃyoga) between the manas and the self (ātman) makes us aware of the pleasure. Suppose, for the sake of argument, that it’s the conjunction (saṃyoga) between the manas and the self (ātman) that also produces the awareness of permanent pleasure. But, since the self is all-pervading, the manas is always conjoined to the self. So, there must be some enabling condition, or auxiliary cause (sahakāri-nimitta), which explains why this conjunction sometimes produces the awareness of permanent pleasure and not always.Footnote 16 More generally, the question is this: if the self does possess permanent pleasure, why is one only aware of it sometimes but not always? As Uddyotakara goes on to note, it’s not easy to escape this line of questioning. For example, the opponent might argue that the mere presence of permanent pleasure itself is sufficient for the conjunction between the self and the manas to produce an awareness of pleasure. But if the awareness of pleasure could arise from this conjunction merely due to the presence of its intentional object, then the contact between the self and the manas could produce the awareness of intentional objects such as colour, etc. merely by depending on those intentional objects themselves. If that were to happen, we would always be flooded with various awareness-events about different intentional objects. Moreover, the agent would always undergo the awareness of permanent pleasure. But, as we’ve seen, that too doesn’t happen.Footnote 17 Therefore, the opponent must explain why the conjunction between the manas and the self only sometimes produces the awareness of permanent pleasure.

When it comes to our ordinary pleasures, our awareness of such pleasures arises from the conjunction between the self and the manas due to the presence of previously accumulated merit. If the opponent now appeals to something like merit to explain how the awareness of permanent pleasure arises, she will face a different challenge. Where does that merit come from? Perhaps, the opponent could say that even a liberated self may have some merit left over from yogic meditative absorption (yoga-samādhi), and that allows us to become aware of this permanent pleasure.Footnote 18 But, since practical undertakings cease completely in the state of liberation, the accumulated merit will run out at some point. At that stage, there will be no awareness of permanent pleasure. If that happens, there will be no difference between that state and the state where there is no permanent pleasure.Footnote 19

Moreover, if the defender of the Permanent Pleasure View insists that the merit doesn’t run out, she needs to explain why that is so. We have strong evidence for the generalization that things that are produced are destroyed; on the basis of that evidence, we can infer that the merit, produced by yogic meditative absorption (yoga-samādhi), should also be destroyed. In contrast, there is no inference to the contrary. One cannot get out of this problem by claiming that the merit itself is permanent, i.e., something that isn’t produced or destroyed. For that implies that the awareness of permanent pleasure is also permanent. Thus, the previously mentioned objection will apply again: namely, that the permanent pleasure will be experienced together with ordinary pleasures and pains.Footnote 20

In response, the defender of the Permanent Pleasure View might try to say that the relation with the body somehow serves as an impediment to the permanent pleasure being experienced at the same time as other pleasures and pains. This view would be extremely bizarre. In the Nyāya picture, the whole purpose of the body is to give rise to experiences of pleasure and pain. So, it’s quite strange to say that the body prevents the experience of pleasure from arising, and, yet, a disembodied being can still experience permanent pleasure.Footnote 21As Vātsyāyana notices, in order to avoid this inelegance, the opponent must say that the body itself is permanent. But that simply contradicts what is observed.Footnote 22

The upshot: the Permanent Pleasure View is hard to defend.Footnote 23

The Problem of Motivation

Even though the Permanent Pleasure View faces these problems, it has a virtue that Vātsyāyana’s view lacks. As we have seen, for Vātsyāyana, liberation is complete freedom from embodied existence. But our embodied existence brings with it lots of different kinds of pleasure. Given that we are at least part-time pleasure-seekers, why should we seek to free ourselves completely from our embodied existence? At a certain juncture, Vātsyāyana himself expresses the thought (albeit as a false awareness) as follows, “With respect to liberation, [there is the false awareness]: ‘This cessation of all effects (kārya) is certainly terrible. Given that liberation involves the loss of everything, many good things disappear. So, how could an intelligent person want that liberation which involves the destruction of all pleasure and is without consciousness?”Footnote 24 There’s a more rigorous way of putting the point. We can be rationally motivated to bring about a state of affairs by means of actions that are themselves painful only if we rationally think (or expect) that realizing that state of affairs will result in some positive payoff, i.e., some desired outcome, which will outweigh the pain that we undergo in bringing it about. If this is true, then we cannot be motivated to realize the state of liberation. For, insofar as the state of liberation involves a perpetual disembodied existence, it involves a loss of all that we value about our lives. So, it doesn’t bring about any desired outcome at all. In contrast, if we were to accept the Permanent Pleasure View, then this problem can be avoided. If the state of liberation involves the manifestation of permanent pleasure but no pain, then it contains an enormous amount of pleasure. Assuming that pleasure is at least one of the things we desire, we can be rationally motivated to seek liberation if we accept this view.

Vātsyāyana is aware of at least a version of this problem. While discussing the Permanent Pleasure View, he considers the objection that “a practical undertaking is for the sake of attaining a desired object (iṣṭa).”Footnote 25 Uddyotakara glosses the objection as follows: “Here, this ordinary person undertakes action for the sake of attaining a desired object. And those who desire liberation undertake actions. For them too, the practical undertaking must be for the sake of attaining a desired object. This very practical undertaking has an end (artha) if there is permanent pleasure in liberation, not otherwise.”Footnote 26 The argument is simply this. All (rational) practical undertakings are motivated by a desire to obtain a desired object. So, (rational) practical undertakings aimed at liberation must also be motivated by a desire to obtain a desired object, i.e., pleasure. That cannot be accounted for on Vātsyāyana’s conception of liberation, since, for him, liberation involves no pleasure. But it can only be explained by appealing to something like the Permanent Pleasure View.

In response, Vātsyāyana rejects the claim that all practical undertakings are motivated by a desire to obtain a desired object, i.e., pleasure.

No, since it is for the sake of the cessation of an undesired object (aniṣṭa). This is the inference: “It is for the sake of attaining a desired object that liberation is taught and that people desirous of liberation undertake action. Both of these aren’t without an end (artha).” And this is unreasonable. It is for the sake of the cessation of an undesired object that liberation is taught and that people desirous of liberation undertake action. Since the desired object isn’t possible without being intertwined with the undesired object, even the desired object ends up being undesired. One who acts in order to avoid an undesired object also avoids the desired object, since it is not possible to avoid one in separation from the other.Footnote 27

In his gloss, Uddyotakara says, “In ordinary people, two kinds of practical undertakings are observed: those for the sake of attaining a desired object, and those for the sake of avoiding an undesired object.”Footnote 28 This response depends on a background picture of motivation. So, let’s expand on this.

As I have already said, within the Nyāya system, a practical undertaking (pravṛtti) is just the commencement (ārambha) of any mental, physical or linguistic action (NS 1.1.20). Vātsyāyana says that the motive (prayojana) underlying any such practical undertaking is an object that causes the practical undertaking in virtue of being determined by the relevant agent as a thing to be attained or avoided: “That, motivated by which the agent undertakes an action, is the motive” (yena prayuktaḥ pravartate tat prayojanam) (NB 3.9 on NS 1.1.1). The thought is explained further later in the commentary on NS 1.1.24, which says, “That in relation to which a person undertakes an action is the motive” (yam artham adhikṛtya pravartate tat prayojanam) (NB 26.14).

If, having determined an object to be something to be attained or avoided, a person performs the act that serves as a means to obtain or to avoid it, then that object is to be understood as the motive. For it is a cause of practical undertakings. The relation (adhikāra) with the object is the determination, “I shall obtain this object, or avoid it.” An object, which is thus determined, is something that the agent is related to.Footnote 29

In his preamble to NS 1.1.1, while motivating the theoretical enterprise of Nyāya, Vātsyāyana seems to explain what the motive is: it is either pleasure and something that brings about pleasure, or pain and something that brings about pain.

Certainly, having apprehended an object by a means of knowing, this subject desires to obtain it, or desires to avoid it. The striving of this subject who is motivated by desire to obtain and desire to avoid is said to be a practical undertaking. Moreover, the success of this is a connection with a result. The one who strives, while desiring to obtain or desiring to avoid that object, either obtains that object or avoids it. The objects are pleasure and the cause of pleasure, and pain and the cause of pain.Footnote 30

If we take these passages seriously, it seems plausible to ascribe a form of psychological hedonism to Vātsyāyana. For Vātsyāyana, an agent can be motivated by two kinds of desire: the desire to obtain pleasure (or a means to pleasure) or the desire to avoid pain (or a means to pain).

The sub-commentator, Uddyotakara, makes this idea explicit in his Nyāya-vārttika:

What, then, is the motive? This is the ordinary meaning: “That, motivated by which a person undertakes an action, is the motive.” What is a person motivated by? Some say, “By righteous conduct (dharma), profit (artha), pleasure (kāma) and liberation.” In contrast, we observe that a person is motivated by the attainment of pleasure and the avoidance of pain. And all objects motivate a conscious being in virtue of being the means to pleasure and pain.Footnote 31,Footnote 32

Slightly later in the same discussion, Uddyotakara refines this picture helpfully by isolating two different kinds of motivational profiles.

People either have attachment, etc. (rāgādi-mat), or are unattached (vīta-rāga). Among them, attachment has the defining characteristic of inclination (abhiṣaṅga) towards an object. Those who have this have attachment, etc. Detachment, in contrast, has the defining characteristic of disinclination (anabhiṣaṅga) from enjoyment (bhoga). Those who have that are unattached. Practical undertakings are of two kinds in accordance with the distinction amongst people. The practical undertakings of those people are of both kinds in accordance with the distinction amongst people. The practical undertakings of an unattached person are of one kind. Amongst those, the practical undertakings that belong to unattached people have as their end (artha) the avoidance of an undesired object. They undertake actions thinking, “We shall avoid something undesired.” But they don’t have any inclination towards anything. The practical undertakings of people who have attachment, etc. are of two kinds. The practical undertakings of these people who have attachment, etc. are of two kinds, either aimed at the acquisition of a desired object, or the avoidance of an undesired object. Thinking, “I shall obtain a desired object,” [a person who has attachment, etc.] undertakes an action due to attachment. Thinking, “I shall avoid an undesired object,” [such a person] abstains due to aversion.Footnote 33

For Uddyotakara, there are two kinds of motivational profiles: attached and unattached. Unattached agents don’t perform any actions in order to obtain pleasure. This is because such unattached agents have no desire for pleasure at all; as Uddyotakara puts it, they are disinclined towards enjoyment. They only perform actions in order to minimize pain. By contrast, attached agents (i.e., those who have attachment, etc.) perform actions for two kinds of reasons: sometimes to obtain pleasure, and at other times merely to avoid pain. This idea is useful in understanding Vātsyāyana’s reply to the problem that we considered above.

In response to that problem, Vātsyāyana pointed out that not all (rational) practical undertakings (even in attached agents like us) are for the sake of attaining a desired object: we are sometimes motivated to act in order to avoid an undesired object like pain, e.g., in the case where we avoid food mixed with honey and poison in order to avoid the deadly consequences of poison. We can use this to explain how someone can be rationally motivated to seek liberation. All of us face a choice between liberation (i.e., permanent disembodied existence) and repeated embodied existence. The pleasure that we undergo in virtue of having a body, the senses, etc. is unavoidably connected to pain. Since it’s not possible to obtain that pleasure without also obtaining the pain that comes with it, the pleasure is to be avoided. The thought is anticipated in Vātsyāyana’s commentary on NS 1.1.2, where he says, “Just as food mixed with honey and poison is not to be obtained, so also pleasure connected to pain is not to be obtained.”Footnote 34 Since the pleasure that is part of embodied existence is connected with pain (either in virtue of being invariably accompanied by it, or in virtue of having the same causes, the same locus or the same subjectFootnote 35), and we can be rationally motivated to act for the sake of avoiding pain, we can be rationally motivated to avoid embodied existence exactly in the same way as one avoids the food mixed with rice and honey. Thus, we have no reason to prefer the Permanent Pleasure View on these grounds.

It’s far from obvious whether this argument succeeds. Suppose, along the lines suggested by Uddyotakara, that we are agents who have attachment, etc. So, we are motivated to act by two kinds of desires: the desire to gain pleasure and things that give rise to pleasure and the desire to avoid pain and things that give rise to pain. These two desires will often pull us in different directions. Suppose, on a night out with friends, I am wondering whether I should order a third gin and tonic. On the one hand, I might be tempted to do so solely because of the breezy joy that gin brings me. On the other hand, I might hesitate, since I worry that I will be mildly hung-over tomorrow. Whether I order the gin and tonic depends on how much weight I attach to these desires. For example, there is no good reason to think that an attached agent like me is rationally required, under these circumstances, act on the desire to avoid the pain that hangovers involve, and refrain from ordering the gin and tonic. If I am predominantly a pleasure-seeker, I will perhaps attach a little less weight to my desire to avoid pain and go ahead and order the gin. And, intuitively, there’s nothing irrational about doing so. Why can’t the case of liberation be exactly like this? Typically, we are motivated by both the desire to attain pleasure and the desire to avoid pain. All of us have lives that are flawed in virtue of being inescapably painful at times. But interspersed between these pains are lots of pleasures that we care about. Provided that we rationally attach suitable weights to our desires to gain pleasure and to avoid pain, we may still rationally forgo liberation and seek to continue our embodied existence. So, unless Vātsyāyana tells us why the correct way of weighing our desires to gain pleasure and to avoid pain will always favour opting for liberation, his solution to the problem raised above cannot be convincing.Footnote 36 In the rest of the essay, I will explain how the solution can be made to work.

Shifting Motivational Profiles

For Vātsyāyana, there is something wrong about the motivational profile of attached agents, i.e., agents who are motivated, in equal if not greater measure, by the desire to obtain pleasure. This is suggested by his defence of a certain principle.

The Pain Principle. We should treat all aspects of embodied existence as pain.Footnote 37

When an attached agent fulfils the requirement laid down by the Pain Principle, she no longer sees anything as pleasant and sees everything as painful. As a result, she is no longer motivated to act for the sake of pleasure, and only desires to avoid pain. Thus, she undergoes a shift in her motivational profile, whereby she transforms into an unattached agent. From this perspective of detachment, she now sees that the only way of getting rid of pain once and for all is to free herself from repeated embodied existence. If I am right, then the Pain Principle gives us an indirect explanation of why even an attached agent should come to seek liberation. In a nutshell, the explanation is this. An attached agent should treat all aspects of embodied existence as pain. Once she does so, she should seek to avoid those aspects (since she also has the desire to avoid pain). That is why she should seek liberation.

Before moving on, it’s worth explaining how this helps us address the worry that I raised at the end of the last section. Consider the gin and tonic example. In that scenario, it seems that I am rationally permitted to order a third gin and tonic because that will bring me pleasure. But Vātsyāyana would say that this is a mistake. If the Pain Principle is true, then I should not even  think that there is any pleasure to be gained from drinking the gin. So, no matter how much weight I actually attach to my desire for pleasure, I cannot rationally let considerations about pleasure play any role in my decision-making. The same goes for our deliberation about whether to continue our embodied existence. If the Pain Principle is true, we should treat all aspects of embodied existence as painful. So, no matter how much weight we actually attach to our desire for pleasure, we cannot rationally continue our embodied existence on the basis of the consideration that it promises to yield pleasure.

Why is the Pain Principle true? In the rest of this section, we shall look at Vātsyāyana’s defence of this principle.

A Contrast: The Naïve Pain Principle

An initial thought might be that the Pain Principle is true, because all aspects of embodied existence in fact are pain. This suggests:

The Naïve Pain Principle. All aspects of embodied existence are pain by their own nature.

The Naïve Pain Principle is a descriptive claim, but the Pain Principle is a normative one. But, using a suitable assumption (e.g., the assumption that, if a claim is true, we should treat it as true), we can explain why the Pain Principle is true by appealing to the Naïve Pain Principle.Footnote 38

However, as Vātsyāyana notes in his commentary before NS 4.1.55, the Naïve Pain Principle is in tension with what we know by perception: all conscious living beings experience pleasure; it’s not possible to deny its existence.

It has been said that “pain is that which has the defining characteristic of distress” (NS 1.1.21). Is this very claim a rejection of pleasure which is experienced within oneself (pratyātma-vedanīya) and is perceived by every living creature, or is it some other alternative? He [i.e., the author of the sūtra] has said that it’s something else. Why? Surely, pleasure, witnessed by all ordinary people, cannot be rejected. Rather, this is a teaching of the cultivation (bhāvana) of the label of pain (duḥkha-saṃjñā), for the sake of avoiding pain, addressed to someone who has become dejected with regard to the pain caused by the experience (anubhava) of the uninterrupted series of births and deaths, and, therefore, desires to avoid pain.Footnote 39

When NS 1.1.21 defines pain as that which has the defining characteristic of distress, Vātsyāyana interprets it as saying that every aspect of embodied existence, including pleasure, counts as pain insofar as it is inextricably connected to pain. But this isn’t supposed to be a literal denial of the existence of pleasure. Rather, it is meant to instruct someone who has become dejected with respect to the pain that is involved in our embodied existence and wishes to avoid it. This person is being taught to cultivate the label of pain with respect to all aspects of our embodied existence. In both Buddhist and non-Buddhist contexts, the term “bhāvana” or “bhāvanā”—which I am translating here as “cultivation”—often refers to the sustained development of a mental state.Footnote 40 When a person is taught to cultivate the label of pain, she is being taught to engage in a sustained development of a mental state where she applies the label of pain to every aspect of embodied existence and thereby perceives everything as pain.

As Vātsyāyana emphasises in his commentary on NS 4.1.58, this isn’t a literal use of the term “pain.” Vātsyāyana here entertains a worry that if one asserts the sentence, “Birth is just pain,” one thereby conveys that there is no pleasure involved in ordinary existence. That is false. The response to the worry is that this is an example of metonymy (upacāra). Here’s the exchange.

[The opponent:] If this is so, why is it not said, “Birth is pain”? If such is to be said, the person who has said the following, “Birth is just pain,” conveys the absence of pleasure.


[Reply:] So, this expression “just” is certainly for the sake of the cessation of birth.


[The opponent:] Why?


[Reply:] Birth isn’t pain in virtue of its own nature, but rather in virtue of a metonymic use (upacāra) of “pain.” The same is also true of pleasure. So, this [birth] is produced by this [pleasure] alone. However, birth is not simply pain.Footnote 41

In his commentary on NS 1.2.14, Vātsyāyana gives an example of metonymy while discussing verbal tricks (chala) in a debate.Footnote 42While describing the reactions of an audience to high melodrama in a play, someone might say, “The benches are crying” (mañcāḥ krośanti). But a quibbler might take this utterance literally, and say, “The people on the benches are crying. But the benches aren’t crying” (mañcasthāḥ puruṣāḥ krośanti, na tu mañcāḥ krośanti). The problem, as Vātsyāyana diagnoses it, is that the hearer construes literally (prādhānyena) an expression—namely, “benches”—that is used in a secondary sense (bhaktyā prayoge). As Vātsyāyana goes on to explain, “Metonymy is characterised by a meaning that is derived (nītārtha) on the basis of accompaniment (saha-caraṇa), etc. The designation (abhidhāna) of an object that possesses something (tad-vat), when it isn’t that thing (atadbhāve), is metonymy.”Footnote 43 Since the benches here are accompanied by the people sitting on them, the people, who possess the benches in virtue of the relation of sitting on them, are referred to or designated by means of the term “benches.” That is why this is an instance of metonymy. The same is true of birth. The term “pain” doesn’t literally refer to “birth.” But pain is an attribute of any birth. So, we can refer to “birth” by using the term “pain” as a metonym. The same goes for pleasure insofar as it is invariably connected to pain.

In his sub-commentary on NS 1.1.21, Uddyotakara gives us some further reasons for thinking that the Naïve Pain Principle is false. The first is an argument from linguistic usage.

Some say that everything is pain by nature. This isn’t right, since it conflicts with perception. For it’s not possible to deny the existence of perceptible pleasure. Suppose it is said that it’s a variety (vikalpa) of pain. Someone might say, “Pleasure is simply a variety (vikalpa) of pain. However, it doesn’t exist [as pain] in virtue of its own nature.” No, since the negative particle (nañ) cannot be applied to a variety [of something]. For it isn’t observed that the negative particle (nañ) is being applied to a variety [of something]. Indeed, with respect to a variety of brahmin, no one applies the term “non-brahmin.” In the same way, the term “non-pain” shouldn’t be applied to a kind of pain.Footnote 44

Pleasure is called “non-pain.” If it were a variety of pain, then we wouldn’t call it “non-pain,” just as we don’t call a brahmin of a certain kind “non-brahmin.” So, pleasure isn’t a kind of pain.

The second argument is more complex.

Moreover, if there were no pleasure, then merit (dharma) would be futile. Since merit is the means to pleasure, merit would be futile in the absence of pleasure. It is not reasonable that the result of merit is the cessation of pain. For, then, given that there would be the undesirable consequence that merit has an absence as its result, merit would have an absence as its result.Footnote 45

If there were no pleasure (but only pain), then there couldn’t be any experience of pleasure, so the merit we may have accumulated by performing virtuous acts would have no effect. And if the result of such actions were only the removal of existing pain, then merit would have an absence as an effect. This contradicts the ordinary manner in which merit is supposed to work: for example, rituals like the new-moon and full-moon sacrifices (darśa-paurṇamāsa) are supposed to produce merit, which, in turn, is supposed to produce a positive effect, e.g., heaven.

The third argument is that, according to Uddyotakara’s theory of practical motivation, there are two different kinds of practical undertakings depending on the underlying motivation.

Moreover, the two-fold-ness of practical undertakings, which is ordinarily observed, wouldn’t exist. One person undertakes action, thinking, “I shall attain a benefit.” The other undertakes action, thinking, “I shall avoid something undesired.” Given that there would be no benefit [i.e., pleasure], there would be no two-fold-ness of practical undertakings in ordinary practice.Footnote 46

Some practical undertakings are motivated by the desire to obtain pleasure, while others are motivated by the desire to avoid pain. This distinction between the two kinds of practical undertakings wouldn’t make sense if everything were just pain by its own nature. Why should we want to keep the distinction? The distinction at least helps us explain the difference between an attached agent and an unattached one. The attached person acts out of both kinds of desires, while the unattached acts only out of the second.

The fourth argument is the most significant. The thought is that the advice that various sages give—namely, that one should treat every aspect of one’s embodied existence as pain—wouldn’t make sense if everything were actually pain.

Furthermore, the cultivation of pain (duḥkḥa-bhāvanā) wouldn’t be taught. For, given that the opposite (pratipakṣa) [i.e., pleasure] would be absent, there would also not be any attachment (sakti) [to pleasure]. Since no one is attached to pain, the cultivation of pain wouldn’t be taught. Therefore, everything is not “pain” in the primary sense. Rather, everything is said to be “pain” by way of teaching the cultivation of pain. Footnote 47

The reason why the advice makes sense is that we in fact experience pleasure, and this experience leads to bad consequences. To counteract those bad consequences, it’s necessary for us to focus on pain. As Uddyotakara notes, if everything were pain, then its opposite, i.e., pleasure, wouldn’t exist. So, there would be no attachment to pleasure. Since no one is attached to things other than pleasure, e.g., pain, Vātsyāyana’s advice that we cultivate the label of pain wouldn’t make much sense either.

While these arguments may show that the Naïve Pain Principle is false, it still doesn’t explain why the Pain Principle is correct.

Three Arguments for the Pain Principle

Vātsyāyana gives at least three arguments for the Pain Principle in his commentary on NS 4.1.55-8.

The first argument is the Argument from Connection. In his commentary on NS 4.1.55—“The production of embodied existence is simply pain due to a connection with various kinds of distress” (vividha-bādhanā-yogād duḥkham eva janmotpattiḥ)—Vātsyāyana argues that, if a person were to notice the many different kinds of distress that embodied beings are subject to, she would (rationally) come to think of both pleasure and the means to pleasure as pain.

Since ‘birth’ means that which is born [rather than the event of being born], it stands for the body, the senses, and awareness-events. The appearance (prādurbhava) of the body and so on, which involve an arrangement of parts, is production. Distress is of various kinds: slight, moderate, and acute. Acute pain belongs to beings in hell, whereas moderate pain belongs to animals. Human beings undergo slight pain, and gods and unattached beings undergo even slighter pain. In this way, for a person who perceives these places of production [i.e., beings born with a body, etc.] as connected to pain, the label (saṃjñā) of pain is established with respect to pleasure and with respect to the body, the senses, and the awareness-events that serve as a means to pleasure. Due to the establishment of the label of pain, a label of disinterestedness (anabhirati) is established with respect to all the realms.Footnote 48 For the person who devotes himself to the label of disinterestedness, thirst (tṛṣṇā) with respect to all the realms is broken. Due to the abandonment of thirst, he is freed from all pain. This is just as in the case of a person, who, taking milk to be poison due to a connection with poison, doesn’t acquire it. As he doesn’t acquire it, he doesn’t attain the pain of death.Footnote 49

The thought depends on the previously discussed analogy of food mixed with poison. Suppose one knows that there is poison in a saucer of milk. One may desire the pleasure of drinking milk, but one also knows that the deadly consequences of poison outweigh the benefits of drinking the milk. In such a scenario, regarding the milk mixed with poison merely as poison and not as milk (and therefore disregarding the benefits of milk) might help one steer clear of it, and thus might prevent one from undergoing the pain of death. In the same way, embodied existence contains both pleasure and pain, but the pain outweighs (both in variety and amount) the pleasure. So, treating all aspects of embodied existence as pain helps us disregard their attractions, and thus allows us to effectively avoid pain that accompanies embodied existence. Regarding all these pleasures as pain loosens our attachment to them. This paves the way for freedom from all suffering. That is why one should treat all aspects of embodied existence as pain.

The second argument is the Argument from Desire. It proceeds from the idea that, if we apprehend pleasure as pleasure, we will end up in more pain than we otherwise would. In his commentary on NS 4.1.57—“For someone who experiences, there is no absence of the cessation of distress due to the defect of seeking” (bādhanā-nivṛtter vedayataḥ paryeṣaṇa-doṣād apratiṣedhaḥ)—Vātsyāyana explains the thought as follows.

Seeking (paryeṣaṇa) is craving (prārthanā), the thirst for obtaining an object. The defect of seeking is this. Someone who experiences [pleasure or a means to pleasure as such] seeks it. That thing which this person seeks either isn’t obtained, or, having been obtained, is endangered. Or, something lesser is obtained, or the object is obtained along with many obstacles. Due to this defect of seeking, there are many kinds of mental sorrow (mānasa-santāpa). In this way, for someone who experiences [pleasure or a means to pleasure as such], there is no cessation of distress due to the defect of seeking. Since the cessation of distress is absent, the cultivation of the label of pain is taught. For this reason, birth is pain, not due to the absence of pleasure.Footnote 50

The argument is this. The experience of pleasure, when one regards it as pleasure, gives rise to more suffering than pleasure. This is because, when one apprehends pleasure as pleasure (or a means to pleasure as a means to pleasure), that apprehension gives rise to cravings, and cravings are never fully satisfied, thus giving rise to many different kinds of mental pain. So, the only way to avoid such pain is to not to apprehend pleasure as pleasure (or a means to pleasure as a means to pleasure) but rather as pain, so that no desire for re-experiencing such pleasure arises again.

The third argument is the Argument from Error. It proceeds from the idea that if we apprehend the pleasure involved in embodied experience as pleasure, we will end up falsely treating even the pain involved in embodied existence as pleasure insofar as it serves as a means to pleasure. In his commentary on NS 4.1.57—“And since there is erroneous awareness of pleasure with respect to a variety of pain” (duḥkhavikalpe sukhābhimānāc ca)—Vātsyāyana explains the thought as follows.

And this person, who abides in pleasure, takes pleasure to be the final aim of human existence, thinking, “There is no highest good other than pleasure, and, when pleasure is attained, one attains one’s end and accomplishes that which was to be accomplished.” On the basis of a false awareness (saṅkalpa), he is attached to pleasure and to the objects that serve as the means to pleasure. Being so attached, he strives for pleasure. For this person who is striving, there arise all the different kinds of pain which are caused by birth, old age, disease, death, contact with undesired objects, separation from desired objects, and the dissatisfaction of cravings. Yet, he is erroneously aware (abhimanyate) of that variety of pain as pleasure. Pain is a constituent element (aṅga) of pleasure. It is not possible to attain pleasure without attaining pain. The person, whose intellect (buddhi) is struck by the perception of pleasure that takes the form, “This is indeed pleasure, since it is a means for attaining that pleasure”, rushes on and doesn’t surpass the cycle of rebirth, following what is said [in the Chāndogya Upaniṣad 5.10.8], “Be born! Die!” The cultivation of the label of pain is taught as an antidote (pratipakṣa) to this label of pleasure. Birth (janman) counts as “pain” due to a connection with pain, not due to an absence of pleasure.Footnote 51

The thought is that we tend to treat even pain as pleasure insofar as it serves as a means to pleasure. That is counterproductive, since it inures us to the painfulness of embodied existence, thereby preventing us from getting out of the cycle of rebirth. So, if we want to avoid this error that perpetuates the pain involved in embodied existence, the best policy for us will be to treat all aspects of embodied existence as pain. We therefore need to cultivate the label of pain with respect to embodied existence, and treat the pleasure involved in embodied existence as pain.

Let’s take stock. If these arguments are sound, then the Pain Principle is true. If we accept the Pain Principle, then we should treat all aspects of embodied existence as pain and therefore must lose all desire for pleasure and objects that give rise to pleasure. As a result, we should only retain our desire to avoid pain. So, our motivational profile should come to match that of an unattached agent. Since liberation involves permanent freedom from pain, we would then be required by rationality to seek liberation. That is how we would be rationally motivated to seek liberation.

Manipulating Desires with Labels

In this last section, I want to argue that the theoretical work that the Pain Principle is supposed to do within Vātsyāyana’s framework reveals something quite general about his theory of human motivation. According to Vātsyāyana, we can transform our motivational profile simply by adopting certain meditative practices where we use certain labels and not others to think about the world and ourselves.

The False Origins of Attachment and Aversion

Vātsyāyana argues that the three defects—attachment, aversion, and delusion—are all based on or involve false awareness of some sort.Footnote 52 Why? Following NS 3.1.26—“No, since attachment and so on have a saṅkalpa as their cause” (na, saṅkalpanimittatvād rāgādīnām)—Vātsyāyana’s story appeals to a mental state called saṅkalpa. He repeats the story at a number of places.

Indeed, it is found that this attachment of living beings that enjoy intentional objects (viṣaya) is produced by a saṅkalpa. And a saṅkalpa has as its origin (yoni) the recollection (anucintana) of intentional objects that experienced earlier.Footnote 53

Attachment and aversion don’t arise in anyone who isn’t deluded. But, in a deluded person, they arise in accordance with a saṅkalpa. The saṅkalpas that are agreeable (rañjanīya) with respect to intentional objects are causes of attachment. The saṅkalpas that are disagreeable (kopanīya) are causes of aversion. And both these kinds of saṅkalpas are nothing other than delusions, since they have the characteristic of being false awareness. These very attachment and aversion have delusion as their origin.Footnote 54

From false saṅkalpa-s that are agreeable, disagreeable and deluding (mohanīya), desire, attachment and delusion arise.Footnote 55

The intentional objects of desire are objects of the senses. That is why they are said to be colour, etc. And, when those are made into objects of false saṅkalpas (mithyāsaṅkalpyamāna), they give rise to attachment, aversion, and delusion.Footnote 56

From these passages, it is clear that, for Vātsyāyana, a saṅkalpa is a false awareness,Footnote 57 which can be of three kinds: agreeable, disagreeable, and deluding. Presumably, when an agent recollects a previously experienced object, she undergoes an awareness-event that portrays that object in a certain way. That is a saṅkalpa. When the saṅkalpa is agreeable, it portrays the object in a pleasing way. Then, it gives rise to attachment towards that and other similar objects. When it is disagreeable, it portrays the object in an unpleasant way. That gives rise to aversion. Finally, when it is deluding, it perhaps portrays the object in an inaccurate way, which in turn gives rise to a delusion. But, since, for Vātsyāyana, any false awareness is a kind of delusion, any saṅkalpa must also count as a delusion. So, attachment and aversion only arise in beings who are deluded in some way. That is why he takes delusion to be the most vicious of the three defects (NB 221.7-8 and 256.14-6 on NS 4.1.6 and NS 4.1.68).

This seems like a radical claim, so let me explain why it might make sense. For Vātsyāyana, delusions are of four kinds: false awareness (mithyā-jñāna), uncertainty (vicikitsā), pride (māna), and confusion (pramāda) (NB 220.7-8 on NS 4.1.3). Amongst these, saṅkalpas fall under the category of false awareness. But do all our attachments and aversion depend on some kind of false awareness? The typology of desire that Vātsyāyana puts forward does seem to suggest this.

Start with attachment. As Vātsyāyana notes, there are five kinds of attachment: lust (kāma), stinginess (matsara), longing (spṛhā), thirst (tṛṣṇā), and greed (lobha). Uddyotakara explains these as follows.

Amongst those, lust is the desire with respect to women; the craving that arises with respect to women is lust. And thus, they have said, “He who doesn’t lust doesn’t rejoice.” The desire not to give up something that isn’t diminished is stinginess; stinginess is the desire not to give up something which, when given away or enjoyed, isn’t diminished, e.g., the desire of the form, “May he not drink the water from the king’s reservoir.” The desire to acquire an unowned object is longing; the desire to obtain an object that isn’t owned is longing. Thirst is the cause of being connected to rebirth; the craving for rebirth is thirst. Greed is the desire to unjustifiably (pramāṇa-viruddha) acquire someone else’s possession; a person who acquires someone else’s possession unjustifiably is called greedy.Footnote 58

Vātsyāyana goes on to explain that the defining characteristic of all these different kinds of attachment is clinging (āsakti), which Uddyotakara glosses as inclination (abhiṣaṅga) towards various objects (NB 220.10; NV 426.1-2).

Let’s move on to aversion. Aversions, for Vātsyāyana, are also of five kinds: anger (krodha), envy (īrṣyā); indignation (asūyā); malice (droha); and vengefulness (amarṣa) (NB 220.7 on NS 4.1.3). Uddyotakara explains these as follows.

Anger is the cause of the agitation of the substrata of the body and the senses; anger is that upon the production of which the substrata of the body and the senses are agitated. Envy is the desire to thwart the adherence (abhiniveśa) of others to a common object; the desire to thwart the adherence of others to that which is common, i.e., unacquired by anyone, is envy. Indignation is impatience with respect to others’ virtues; the impatience that arises after one hears about others’ virtues is indignation. Malice is the desire to harm others; the desire of an incapable person to harm others is malice. Vengefulness is the intolerance of someone who has been harmed; the intolerance of someone who has been harmed is vengefulness.Footnote 59

Vātsyāyana goes on to explain that the defining characteristic of all these different kinds of aversion is non-endurance (amarṣa), which Uddyotakara takes to be a form of intolerance with respect to pain and the means to pain (NB 220.10; NV 426.2).Footnote 60

For Vātsyāyana, all these attachments and aversions are based on a mistake either about the objects of the senses that we are attached or averse to, or about ourselves. In some of these cases, the explanation might be obvious. For example, in the case of stinginess or greed or jealousy, the desire may be driven by a false belief about who should be or is the rightful owner of an object; similarly, indignation may be based on a false belief about one’s own superiority, malice may be based on the false belief that one can harm another person, and vengefulness may be based on the false idea that one harmful act can compensate or undo the effects of another harmful act. What I want to focus on is Vātsyāyana’s treatment of two kinds of attachment: the first is thirst (tṛṣṇā), i.e., the desire for rebirth, and the second is lust (kāma), i.e., sexual desire.

Thirst and Lust

Let’s begin with thirst. In his preamble to NS 4.2.1, Vātsyāyana claims that the kind of true awareness that helps us escape the cycle of rebirth can’t be about everything. It is directed at a certain object whose nature, when concealed from us by some false awareness, gives rise to the cycle of rebirth and therefore to all our suffering.Footnote 61 What is that false awareness? Vātsyāyana’s reply: It’s a false awareness about the self. When the nature of the self is hidden from us by this false awareness, we come to have the desire to be born again. This leads to rebirth. Vātsyāyana describes the nature of this false awareness as follows.

It is the ego-construction (ahaṅkāra), i.e., the delusion that is the apprehension of the self in what is not the self and takes the form, “I exist.” The ego-construction is the view of someone who undergoes a perception, “I exist,” with respect to what is not the self.

[The opponent:] What are the objects about which there is ego-construction?

[Reply:] The body, the senses, the manas, the hedonic states (vedanā), and the awareness-events.

[The opponent:] How is ego-construction about them the root of the cycle of rebirth?

[Reply:] Indeed, this person who determines, “I exist,” with respect to things such as the body, etc., is overwhelmed by a thirst for their non-destruction insofar as he thinks that their destruction is his own destruction, and appropriates them over and over again. Having appropriated them, he proceeds to be born and to die. Since he can’t surpass that, he isn’t completely freed from pain.Footnote 62

On Vātsyāyana’s view, the kind of false awareness that gives rise to the cycle of rebirth is ego-construction, i.e., a false awareness about oneself. Since we identify ourselves with the body, the senses, the manas, the hedonic states, awareness-events, etc., we take our own existence to be tied up with their existence. Now, we don’t want our own destruction. This, presumably, is explained by our desire for pleasure: if we want pleasure and if our own existence is our only means of getting it, we should want our own existence to continue. Then, given that we take ourselves to be our body, etc., we also want the body, etc. not to be destroyed. This gives rise to thirst, i.e., the desire for embodied existence, which causes us to be born again and again.

Consider now the second example: lust or sexual desire. In this case, the desire arises from a failure to see the object of desire for what it is. In his commentary on NS 4.2.3—“The cause of those [defects] is an erroneous awareness with respect to partite objects” (tan-nimittaṃ tv avayavy-abhimānaḥ)—Vātsyāyana writes:

The cause of those defects, then, is an erroneous awareness with respect to partite objects. Indeed, in men, that consists in the label “woman”, along with all its dressings (sa-pariṣkara). And in women, it’s the label “man.” In contrast, the dressing consists in a label based on marks (nimitta- saṃjñā) and a label based on secondary characteristics (anuvyañjana-saṃjñā). A label based on a mark is of the following sort: “tongue” and “ears”, “teeth” and “lips”, “eye” and “nose.” A label based on secondary characteristics takes the form, “The teeth are like this,” “The lips are like this.” Since this very label enhances the attachment that is lust, and gives rise to defects that are connected to it, it is to be abandoned.Footnote 63

The idea seems to be this. Sexual desire arises from applying certain concepts or labels to certain material objects. The person may apply the label “man” or “woman” to a certain body, along with a number of other concepts.Footnote 64 Uddyotakara explains:

Moreover, even in that case, there are two labels: a label based on a mark and a label based on a secondary characteristic. A label that is based on a mark is of the following sort: “teeth” and “lips,” etc. The label that applies to teeth, etc. on the basis of tooth-hood, etc. is a label based on a mark. And, similarly, a label that is based on a secondary characteristic involves the projection (adhyāropa) of something on to the mark in the form, “It is thus”: “The teeth are thus,” “The two lips are thus,” etc. This very label, which is cultivated by means of a projection, is a delusion.Footnote 65

Some of these may be labels based on marks (nimitta) of a man’s or a woman’s body, e.g., their teeth, their lips, etc., which the subject identifies on the basis of their defining characteristics or marks, such as tooth-hood. But some of the others may be labels based on secondary characteristics (anuvyañjana). For example, one takes one’s lover’s teeth to be a string of pearls, the application of the concept “string of pearls” will be a label based on a secondary characteristic, i.e., a similarity with other objects. The application of these latter labels, as Uddyotakara notes, always involve delusion, since they involve projection of properties that are in fact absent from the relevant objects. Since these labels allegedly create sexual desire, they are to be abandoned.

Cultivating Labels

How can we get rid of these kinds of attachment and aversion? In his commentary on NS 4.2.2, Vātsyāyana explains the process as follows.

First, meditate on them [the objects of the senses]. And for one who reflects on them, the false saṅkalpa about colour, etc. ceases. When that ceases, reflect on the body, etc. in relation to the self. From the meditative awareness (prasaṃkhyāna) of that, the ego-construction with respect to oneself ceases. This person, who roams with a mind that detached from himself and the world outside, is said to be free.Footnote 66

In his explanation of this passage, Uddyotakara says that our ordinary attachments towards our own material possessions are based on the thought that there is something special about these material possessions insofar as they belong only to us. We think, “These are just mine.” But the awareness that undermines that false judgement has the content: “These are not mine; they are shared just like something to be used for purposes of worship, or something that is stolen, or fire, or something that is inherited, etc.”Footnote 67 The thought, then, is that, by discovering the nature of objects of the senses, we can get rid of some of our attachments. However, in order to undermine other attachments e.g., the thirst for rebirth, we will have to meditate on the nature of the body, the senses, the manas, etc. Here, we need a different kind of meditative awareness. As Uddyotakara puts it, “The meditative awareness is the perception of distinctness with respect to the body, etc. in the form, ‘These are not selves.’”Footnote 68

In relation to lust, Vātsyāyana offers the following advice. We can overcome the negative effects of the labels that give rise to sexual desire by cultivating foul labels (aśubha-saṁjñā).Footnote 69 Foul labels raise to salience certain features of the body that elicit disgust.

However, their abandonment consists in a label based on parts by means of distinguishing them, e.g., a label such as “hair on the head”, “body-hair”, “flesh”, “blood”, “bones”, “ligaments”, “veins”, “phlegm”, “bile”, “excrement”, etc. That label is said to be a foul label (aśubha-saṁjñā). A person who cultivates it loses the attachment that is lust.Footnote 70

By cultivating foul labels with regard to the body, one comes to see the body really to be the foul object that it is, i.e., a mass of hair, flesh, blood, bones, ligaments, veins, etc. Since these labels elicit disgust instead of lust, they can serve as the antidote to lust.

Interestingly, the work that foul labels do in undermining lust can be carried out by the label of pain with respect to thirst. As we saw earlier, Vātsyāyana thinks that we should apply the label “pain” to all aspects of embodied existence in order to induce a motivational shift, such that we first become disinterested with respect to all the realms, and then lose our thirst with respect to all the realms. Recall what he says in his commentary on NS 4.1.55:

In this way, for a person who perceives these places of production [i.e., beings born with a body, etc.] as connected with pain, the label (saṃjñā) of pain is established with respect to pleasure and with respect to the body, the senses, and the awareness-events that serve as a means to pleasure. Due to the establishment of the label of pain, there will be a label of disinterestedness (anabhirati) with respect to all the realms. For the person who devotes himself to the label of detachment, thirst with respect to all the realms is broken. Due to the abandonment of thirst, he is freed from all pain.Footnote 71

This passage suggests that the primary function of applying the label of pain to all aspects of embodied existence is to undermine a specific kind of attachment, namely thirst. Vātsyāyana in fact revisits the point again in his preamble to NS 4.2.1. After arguing that the conflation of the self with the body and so on generates thirst, he says:

However, he who perceives pain, the basis of pain, and the pleasure that is connected to pain in the form, “This is all pain,” is comprehensively aware of (parijānāti) pain. And the pain, when comprehensively apprehended (parijñāta), ceases. For it isn’t obtained, like food mixed with poison. In this way, he perceives the defects and the karmic factors as causes of pain. Moreover, since it isn’t possible to destroy the uninterrupted series of pains unless the defects cease, he avoids the defects. Furthermore, when the defects have ceased, it has been said, “there is no practical undertaking for the sake of rebirth (pratisandhāna) in a being whose defilements have been destroyed” (NS 4.1.64).Footnote 72

The lesson is supposed to be this. Just as the foul labels are useful for undermining the false awareness that underlies sexual desire, so also the label of pain is useful for undermining a number of errors about pain. An ordinary human being labours under the misconception that she is her body, her senses, etc. Insofar as she desires her own continued existence, she desires to be born again and again. This is thirst. However, a person who is subject to thirst misunderstands the nature of the pain that she undergoes. She takes the pain that necessarily accompanies embodied existence to be a necessary evil that she must accept in order to obtain the pleasure that she truly values. As we saw in our discussion of the arguments for the Pain Principle, either this person fails to realize how our attachment to pleasure gives rise to pain that outweighs the pleasure in variety and amount, or how our experiences of pleasure as pleasure gives rise to more pain, or how our attachment to pleasure misleads us into thinking of pain as pleasure. However, applying the label “pain” to all aspects of embodied existence serves as an antidote to all these errors. This, in turn, gives rise to a comprehensive awareness (parijñāna) of pain. This ultimately undermines our desire for rebirth.

The contrast between sexual desire and thirst lies in this. While the antidote to sexual desire requires us to focus on foul labels that correctly describe the objects of sexual desire, the label of pain doesn’t correctly describe all aspects of embodied existence. In fact, Vātsyāyana himself thinks that the application of the label of pain to all aspects of embodied existence involves treating something that isn’t literally pain as pain. So, this is simply meant to be a useful delusion that can undo the foundations of our attachment to pleasure. This suggests that, on this view, a false awareness can be a guide to the truth about pain.

The upshot is this. Vātsyāyana believes that some of our desires—which are either forms of attachment or of aversion—are invariably based on some false awareness which obscures or conceals the true nature of the object of desire. The only way to get rid of them is to meditate on (i.e., repeatedly think about or focus on) these objects by means of certain labels. By manipulating the labels using which we think about such objects, we can get rid of those desires.

Conclusion

In this essay, I have explained Vātsyāyana’s solution to a problem that arises for his theory of liberation. For him, liberation is a permanent state of disembodiment: it involves absolute cessation of pain, but, as a result, also involves absolute cessation of pleasure. The problem was this: How can agents like us—who habitually seek pleasure—be rationally motivated to seek liberation? Vātsyāyana’s solution depends on what I called the Pain Principle, the principle that we should treat all aspects of our embodied existence as pain. If we follow this advice, we will come to apply the label of “pain” to all aspects of our embodied existence, including pleasure. This in turn is supposed to undermine our attachment to our own embodied existence. As I went on to argue, this fits with a general theory of human motivation that Vātsyāyana defends, namely that, by manipulating the labels using which we think about the world and ourselves, we can induce radical shifts in our patterns of motivation.