Skip to main content
Log in

Freud and Heidegger on the ‘Origins’ of Sexuality

  • Theoretical/Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While Freud and Heidegger were antipathetic towards one another’s ideas, a number of commentators have argued that the Freud–Heidegger relation is actually quite complementary. This paper contributes to this position by engaging with the relationship through the mediation of their respective views on the ‘origins’ of sexuality; a topic that is implicit to Freudian psychoanalytic theory and which is often taken to be absent from Heidegger’s, with the consequence that it has been ignored when bringing them into conversation. Having shown that in the 1928 lecture course The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, Heidegger does in fact address the question of sexuality in relation to the neutrality of Dasein outlined in the previous year’s Being and Time, I (1) bring Freud and Heidegger into conversation on the question of the ‘origins’ of sexuality to suggest that there is a strong affinity between the two on this issue, insofar as both (2) argue against any form of sexual essentialism by depending upon a processual (rather than substantial) ontology and affirming an originary sexual indeterminateness, which in the case of Freud takes the form of an initial bisexuality and in the case of Heidegger an ontological sexual neutrality, before (3) concluding that, while Freud’s initial bisexuality forecloses sexuality within a binary framework, Heidegger’s notion of an ontological sexual neutrality does not, and so goes furthest in laying the ground for a rethinking of sexuality in non-essentialist, non-binary terms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Heidegger’s (1989) discussion of ‘enowning’ (Ereignis).

  2. For example, in the Letter on Humanism, from 1947, Heidegger criticizes ‘metaphysics’ because it denotes a mode of thinking that (1) is based on and enclosed within a prior assumed conception of Being (1977: 226), (2) takes certain truths to be self-evident (1977: 225), and (3) is trapped within a logic of binary oppositions (1977: 232). For an extended discussion of this text and issue, see Rae (2014).

  3. It is for this reason that Ben Vedder’s (1998) attempt to develop an ontic account of sexuality from Heidegger’s comments on ‘desire’ in his early seminars on Aristotle (2009: 61, 72) and the Ancient Greeks (2008: 228) flounders. As Vedder (1998: 9) admits, strictly speaking Heidegger does not talk of ‘desire’ in either his early or later works, with the consequence that Vedder uses similes (striving, willing, insufficiency, giving, thanking, and so on) to develop a Heideggerian account of ‘desire’. Putting to one side the validity of those conflations, Vedder therefore only provides an account of desire in Heidegger by collapsing the particularity of distinct concepts and experiences under the universal term ‘desire’ and then, presumably, also conflating this with sexuality. This, however, ignores the fundamental lesson of Heidegger’s analysis: each ontic expression (of sexuality) is unique, particular, and ever-changing based on the configuration of Being’s becoming subtending it; it cannot be subsumed under a universal a priori definition or preconception. It is for this reason that Kevin Aho’s (2005) claim that a substantive account of sexuality can be gleaned from Heidegger’s return to the question of the (ontic) body in his later Zollikon Seminars (2001) is also problematic. Not only does Aho fail to explain the connection between the body and sexuality—a topic that Heidegger does not explicitly broach in the Zollikon Seminars—but it also risks treating the body and, by extension, sexuality as universal categories rather than as a distinctly singular phenomenon. In order to let each ‘thing’ reveal itself as it is in its concrete, particular, determinations, Heidegger cannot and does not provide a determinate account of the body or sexuality per se, instead focusing on the ontological understanding that we, the phenomenologist, must ‘adopt’ to allow each phenomena to reveal itself in its concrete form, rather than as how we wish to see it or have been taught to do so.

References

  • Aho, K. A. (2005). The missing dialogue between Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty: On the importance of the Zollikon Seminars. Body and Society,11(2), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Askay, R. (1999). A philosophical dialogue between Heidegger and Freud. Journal of Philosophical Research,24, 415–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Askay, R. (2001). Heidegger’s philosophy and its implications for psychology, Freud, and existential psychoanalysis. In M. Heidegger & M. Boss (Eds.), Zollikon seminars: Protocols-conversations-letters (pp. 301–316) (F. Mayr & R. Askay, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Askay, R., & Farquhar, J. (2006). Apprehending the inaccessible: Freudian psychoanalysis and existential phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Askay, R., & Farquhar, J. (2013). Being unconscious: Heidegger and Freud. In K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. G. T. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Z. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, & T. Thornton (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry (pp. 1227–1244). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartky, S. L. (1970). Originative thinking in the later philosophy of Heidegger. Philosophy and Phenomenological Review,30(3), 368–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boothby, R. (2001). Freud as philosopher: Metapsychology after Lacan. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boss, M. (1963). Psychoanalysis and Daseinanalysis (Ludwig B. Lefebvre, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.

  • Chanter, T. (2001). The problematic normative assumptions of Heidegger’s ontology. In N. J. Holland & P. Huntington (Eds.), Feminist interpretations of Martin Heidegger (pp. 73–108). Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (2008). The human and the hidden: Existential wonderings about depth, soul, and the unconscious. The Humanistic Psychologist,36, 227–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, A. I. (2001). The emergence of sexuality: Historical epistemology and the formation of concepts. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (2008). Geschlecht I: Sexual difference, ontological difference. In P. Kamuf & E. Rottenberg (Eds.), Psyche: Inventions of the other (Vol. II, pp. 7–26) (Ruben Bevezdivin and Elizabeth Rottenberg, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Escudero, J. A. (2015). Heidegger and the hermeneutics of the body. International Journal of Gender and Women’s Studies,3(1), 16–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrell-Krell, D. (1992). Das Unheimliche: Architectural sections of Heidegger and Freud. Research in Phenomenology,22, 43–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (2000). Three essays on sexuality, the standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 3) (James Strachey, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.

  • Glazebrook, T. (2001). Heidegger and Ecofeminism. In N. J. Holland & P. Huntington (Eds.), Feminist interpretations of Martin Heidegger (pp. 221–251). Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graybeal, J. M. (1990). Language and “the Feminine” in Nietzsche and Heidegger. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Heidegger, M. (1977). Letter on humanism. In D. Farrell-Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (pp. 217–266) (Frank A. Capuzzi in collaboration with J. Glenn Gray, Trans.). London: Harper Perennial.

  • Heidegger, M. (1984). The metaphysical foundations of logic (Michael Heim, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1989). Contributions to philosophy (from enowning) (Parvis Emad and Kenneith May, Trans.). Bloomington: Indianapolis University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Zollikon seminars: Protocols-conversations-letters. In M. Boss (Ed.) (Franz Mayr and Richard Askay, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Basic concepts of ancient philosophy (Richard Rojcewicz, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2009). Basic concepts of Aristotlean philosophy (Robert D. Metcalf & Mark B. Tanzer, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Huntington, P. (1998). Ecstatic subjects, Utopia, and recognition: Kristeva, Heidegger, Irigaray. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huntington, P. (2001). Introduction I—General background history of the feminist reception of Heidegger and a guide to Heidegger’s thought. In N. J. Holland & P. Huntington (Eds.), Feminist interpretations of Martin Heidegger (pp. 1–42). Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, J. M. (2007). Questioning and the materiality of crisis: Freud and Heidegger. Philosophy and Social Criticism,33(2), 251–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2012). Being and technology: Heidegger on the overcoming of metaphysics. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology,43(3), 305–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2013). Overcoming philosophy: Heidegger on the destruction of metaphysics and the transformation to thinking. Human Studies,36(2), 235–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2014). Ontology in Heidegger and Deleuze. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, W. J. (2003). Heidegger and psychoanalysis? Natureza Humana,5(1), 9–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, G. (1975). The traffic in women: Notes on the “political economy” of sex. In L. Nicholson (Ed.), The second wave: A reader in feminist theory (pp. 27–62). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, G. (1984). Thinking sex: Notes for a radical theory of the politics of sexuality. In C. S. Vance (Ed.), Pleasure and danger: Exploring feminist sexuality (pp. 267–319). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (2003). Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology (Hazel E. Barnes, Trans.). New York: Routledge.

  • Ştefan, I. (2016). Authenticity of human behaviour in Freud and Heidegger. AGATHOS,7(2), 50–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vedder, B. (1998). Heidegger on desire. Continental Philosophy Review,31(4), 353–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, D. (2002). Reading Heidegger responsibly: Glimpses of being in Dasein’s development. In F. Raffoul & D. Pettigrew (Eds.), Heidegger and practical philosophy (pp. 219–236). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the three reviewers for their generous and stimulating comments on previous versions of this paper.

Funding

This paper forms part of the activities for the Conex Marie Skłodowska-Curie Research Project ‘Sovereignty and Law: Between Ethics and Politics’ (2013–00415–026), co-funded by the Universidad Carlos III de Madrid, the European Union’s Seventh Framework Program for Research, Technological Development and Demonstration under Grant Agreement 600371, The Spanish Ministry of the Economy and Competitivity (COFUND2013–40258), The Spanish Ministry for Education, Culture, and Sport (CEI–15–17), and Banco Santander. More information about the project can be found at https://sovereigntyandlaw.wordpress.com/.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gavin Rae.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rae, G. Freud and Heidegger on the ‘Origins’ of Sexuality. Hum Stud 42, 543–563 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-019-09525-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-019-09525-3

Keywords

Navigation