Methodology in Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation

Article
  • 87 Downloads

Abstract

Aristotle’s theory of spontaneous generation offers many puzzles to those who wish to understand his theory both within the context of his biology and within the context of his more general philosophy of nature. In this paper, I approach the difficult and vague elements of Aristotle’s account of spontaneous generation not as weaknesses, but as opportunities for an interesting glimpse into the thought of an early scientist struggling to reconcile evidence and theory. The paper has two goals: (1) to give as charitable and full an account as possible of what Aristotle’s theory of spontaneous generation was, and to examine some of its consequences; and (2) to reflect on Aristotle as a scientist, and what his comments reveal about how he approached a difficult problem. In particular, I propose that the well-recognized problem of the incompatibility between Aristotle’s concept of spontaneity and his theory of spontaneous generation presents an opportunity for insight into his scientific methodology when approaching ill-understood phenomena.

Keywords

Aristotle Spontaneous generation Spontaneity Methodology 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Balme, D. M. 1962. “Development of Biology in Aristotle and Theophrastus: Theory of Spontaneous Generation.” Phronesis 7(1): 91–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Balme, D. M. 1992. Aristotle: De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with passages from II.13). Clarendon Aristotle Series. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  3. Barnes, J. (Ed.). 1993. Aristotle: Posterior Analytics. (J. Barnes, Trans.) 2nd Ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  4. Freudenthal, G. 1995. Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  5. Gotthelf, A. 1989. “Teleology and Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle: A Discussion.” T. Penner and R. Kraut (eds.), Nature, Knowledge, and Virtue: Essays in Memory of Joan Kung, Apeiron. Vol. 22(4). Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing, pp. 181–193.Google Scholar
  6. Hardie, R. P. and Gaye, R. K. 1984. “Physics.” J. Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Vol. One. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Henry, D. 2003. “Themistius and Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 24(Summer 2003): 183–207.Google Scholar
  8. Hett, W. S. 1957. Aristotle: On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath. Loeb Classical Library. Revised Ed., Vol. 288. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Hull, D. L. 1967a. “The Conflict Between Spontaneous Generation and Aristotle’s Metaphysics.” Actes du VIIe Congrès Interaméricaine de Philosophie. Quebec: Université Laval, pp. 245–250.Google Scholar
  10. Hull, D. L. 1967b. “The Metaphysics of Evolution.” The British Journal for the History of Science 3(4): 309–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Johnson, M. R. 2009. “Spontaneity, Democritean Causality and Freedom.” Elenchos: Revista di studi sul pensiero antico 30(1): 5–52.Google Scholar
  12. Johnson, M. R. 2012. “The Medical Background of Aristotle’s Theory of Nature and Spontaneity.” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 27: 105–152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Kirk, G. S., Raven, J. E. and Schofield, M. 2007. The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection Texts. 2nd Ed. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Kruk, R. 1990. “A Frothy Bubble: Spontaneous Generation in the Medieval Islamic Tradition.” Journal of Semitic Studies 35(2): 265–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Lennox, J. G. 2001. “Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle’s Theory of Spontaneous Generation.” J. G. Lennox (ed.), Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 229–249.Google Scholar
  16. Leroi, A. M. 2014. The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
  17. Lloyd, G. E. 1996. “Spontaneous Generation and Metamorphosis.” G. E. Lloyd (ed.), Aristotelian Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 104–125.Google Scholar
  18. McCartney, E. S. 1920. “Spontaneous Generation and Kindred Notions in Antiquity.” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 51: 101–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Panayides, C. 2013. “Aristotle on Chance and Spontaneous Generation: A Discussion Note.” Filozofia 68(2): 114–123.Google Scholar
  20. Peck, A. L. 1942. Aristotle: Generation of Animals. Loeb Classical Library. Vol. 366. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Peck, A. L. 1970. Aristotle: Historia Animalium, Books IVVI. Loeb Classical Library. Vol. 438. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Ross, W. D. 1936. Aristotle’s Physics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  23. Solmsen, F. 1957. “The Vital Heat, the Inborn Pneuma and the Aether.” The Journal of Hellenic Studies 77(1): 119–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Stavrianeas, S. 2008. “Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle’s Biology.” Rhizai: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 2: 303–338.Google Scholar
  25. Tredennick, H. 1933. Aristotle: Metaphysics, Books IIX. Loeb Classical Library. Vol. 271. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Vartanian, A. 1973. “Spontaneous Generation.” P. P. Wiener (ed.), Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Drake UniversityDes MoinesUSA

Personalised recommendations