Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Reimagining Childhood: Responding to the Challenge Presented by Severe Developmental Disability

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Through an exploration of the experience of severe and profound intellectual disability, this essay will attempt to expose the predominant, yet usually obscured, medical anthropology of the child and examine its effects on pediatric bioethics. I will argue that both modern western society and modern western medicine do, actually, have a robust notion of the child, a notion which can find its roots in three influential thinkers: Aristotle, Immanuel Kant and Jean Piaget. Together, these philosophers offer us a compelling vision: the child is primarily a future rational, autonomous adult. While this tacit understanding has arguably widespread effects on such things as our concept of good parenting, of proper schooling, and so on, I will focus on the effect is has on the treatment of children with severe developmental disabilities. When examined in light of this population, the dominant medical anthropology of the child will be shown to be deficient. Instead, I argue for an expansion—indeed, a full reimagining—of our notions of childhood, not only to re-infuse dignity into the lives of children with SDD, but to better represent the goods of childhood, generally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Notably, severe developmental disability is not just a challenge to our notion of childhood, but insofar as our notions of childhood are directly derivative of specific notions of proper adulthood, they also challenge our dominant frameworks of personhood, generally.

  2. Certainly the influence could be traced back to many additional sources, as well, but these three have been chosen as playing a particularly instrumental role in the construction of our modern understanding.

  3. The notion of child as an “incomplete” or a “not yet” adult emerges in other influential texts. For example, in Centuries of Childhood (1962) Phillipe Aries, a French historian, notably argues that “childhood” is actually a modern concept, first emerging in the 17th century, instead of the enduring, objective life stage we think it is. By analyzing paintings and writings from the Middle Ages, he concluded that Medieval society did not view childhood as a distinct period of life; instead, children were merely small, inadequate adults, lacking in the capacities of adulthood.

  4. The centrality of rationality and freedom figure prominently in many other influential modern philosophers’ notions of childhood, as well. Notably, liberal 17th century philosopher John Locke in Some Thoughts Concerning Education and Of the Conduct of Understanding believed that because a child’s mind was a “blank slate” until it had worldly experience, a child was trainable and, therefore, an emergent free individual (1996). Even distinctly feminist existentialists like Simone de Beauvoir (1948) hold freedom as a centering value, emphasizing the existence of the individual person as a free and responsible agent.

  5. Beyond medicine, several philosophers have explored the dangers of a “hyper-cognitive” view for moral philosophy and moral status specifically. In particular, see Stephen Post’s The Moral Challenges of Alzheimer Disease (1995), which challenges the modern philosophical trend of premising moral obligations on cognitive functions from the perspective of care for those with dementia and Eva Feder Kittay and Licia Carlson’s Cognitive Disability and its Challenge to Moral Philosophy, where Kittay draws on her experience of parenting Sesha to critically engage the “hyper-cognitive” arguments mounted by Peter Singer and Jeff McMahan.

  6. It should be noted that the AAP, in particular, has given much attention to the needs of children and families with developmental disabilities, advocating for early identification and surveillance, the availability of more comprehensive services and resources and patient- and family-centered care coordination (see AAP Council on Children with Disabilities 2006, 2014, 2016). This work has been essential in coordinating quality care for children and families but it still relies unreflectively on a particular, impoverished notion of childhood which, although certainly unintentional, has still had negative impacts on this population, in particular.

  7. Many sociologists have even argued that childhood has its own culture, one distinct and not derivative from adult culture, based largely in the activities of imaginative and unstructured play (James et al. 2004, pp. 81–100).

References

  • AAP Committee on Adolescence. (2016). Achieving quality health services for adolescents. Pediatrics, 138(2). doi:10.1542/peds.2016-1347.

  • AAP Committee on Bioethics. (2016). Informed consent in decision-making in pediatric practice. Pediatrics, 138(2). doi:10.1542/peds.2016-1484.

  • AAP Council on Disabilities. (2006). Identifying infants and young children with developmental disorders in the medical home: An algorithm for developmental surveillance and screening. Pediatrics, 118(1), 405–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • AAP Council on Disabilities. (2014). Patient- and family-centered care coordination: A framework for integrating care for children and youth across multiple systems. Pediatrics, 133(5), e1451–e1460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • AAP Council on Disabilities. (2016). Recognition and management of medical complexity. Pediatrics, 138(6), e1–e13.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Medical Association. (2006). Surrogate decision making. In American Medical Association Code of Medical Ethics. Chicago: American Medical Association.

  • Aries, P. (1962). Centuries of childhood: A social history of family life (trans: Baldick, R.). New York: Vintage Books.

  • Arpaly, N. (2002). Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (2008). Principles of biomedical ethics (6th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauvoir, S. (1948). The ethics of ambiguity. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, C. A., Boulet, S., Schieve, L. A., Cohen, R. A., Blumberg, S., Yeargin-Allsopp, M., et al. (2011). Trends in the prevalence of developmental disabilities in US children, 1997–2008. Pediatrics, 127(6), 1034–1042.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. E., & Brock, D. W. (1989). Deciding for others: The ethics of surrogate decision making. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, S. (1998). Aidan’s way. Naperville, IL: Source Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (2009). The philosophical baby. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, J., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2010). Three-month-olds show a negativity bias in their social evaluations. Developmental Science, 13(6), 923–926.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, J., Wynn, K., Bloom, P., & Mahajan, N. (2011). How infants and toddlers react to antisocial others. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 108(50), 19931–19936.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, A., Jenks, C., & Prout, A. (2004). Theorizing childhood. Oxford: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janvier, A., Bauer, K. L., & Lantos, J. (2007). Are newborns morally different from other children? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 28(5), 413–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janvier, A., LeBlanc, I., & Barrington, K. (2008). The best interest standard is not applied for neonatal resuscitation decisions. Pediatrics, 121(5), 963–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jennings, B. (2016). Reconceptualizing autonomy: A relational turn in bioethics. Hastings Center Report, 46(3), 11–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1898). Critique of practical reason. In T. K. Abbott (Trans.), Kant’s critique of practical reason and other works on the theory of ethics. London: Longmans, Green & Co.

  • Kant, I. (1970). Kant’s political writings (trans: Nisbet, H. B.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kant, I. (2003). On education (trans: Churton, A.). Mineola, NY: Dover.

  • Katz, A. L., Webb, S. A., & AAP Committee on Bioethics. (2016). Informed consent in decision-making in pediatric practice. Pediatrics, 138(2). doi:10.1542/peds.2016-1485.

  • Kittay, E. F. (1999). Love’s labor: Essays on women, equality and dependency. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levetown, M., & AAP Committee on Bioethics. (2008). Communicating with children and families: From everyday interactions to skill in conveying distressing information. Pediatrics, 121(5), e1441–e1460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1996). Some thoughts concerning education and Of the conduct of understanding. R. Grant & N. Tarcov (Eds.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Macleod, C. (2010). Primary goods, capabilities and children. In I. Robeyns & H. Bridghouse (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masschelein, J. (2004). How to conceive of critical educational theory today? Journal of Philosophy of Education, 38(3), 351–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G. (2008). Getting beyond the deficit conception of childhood: Thinking philosophically with children. In M. Hand & C. Winstanley (Eds.), Philosophy in schools (pp. 27–40). London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G. (2009). Philosophy and developmental psychology: Outgrowing the deficit conception of childhood. In H. Siegel (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of education (pp. 162–176). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, A. (1990). Is akratic action always irrational? In A. Rorty & O. Flanagan (Eds.), Identity, character, and morality (pp. 379–400). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Payne, K. J., & Ross, L. M. (2009). Simplicity parenting: Using the extraordinary power of less to raise calmer, happier and more secure kids. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1936). Origins of intelligence in the child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salter, E. (2014). Resisting the siren call of individualism in pediatric decision making. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 39(1), 26–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A., White, D., & Arnold, R. (2013). Uncertainty: The other side of prognosis. New England Journal of Medicine, 368(26), 2448–2450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stables, A. (2008). Childhood and the philosophy of education. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erica K. Salter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Salter, E.K. Reimagining Childhood: Responding to the Challenge Presented by Severe Developmental Disability. HEC Forum 29, 241–256 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-017-9331-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-017-9331-6

Keywords

Navigation