Skip to main content
Log in

Derivation of Classical Mechanics in an Energetic Framework via Conservation and Relativity

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The notions of conservation and relativity lie at the heart of classical mechanics, and were critical to its early development. However, in Newton’s theory of mechanics, these symmetry principles were eclipsed by domain-specific laws. In view of the importance of symmetry principles in elucidating the structure of physical theories, it is natural to ask to what extent conservation and relativity determine the structure of mechanics. In this paper, we address this question by deriving classical mechanics—both nonrelativistic and relativistic—using relativity and conservation as the primary guiding principles. The derivation proceeds in three distinct steps. First, conservation and relativity are used to derive the asymptotically conserved quantities of motion. Second, in order that energy and momentum be continuously conserved, the mechanical system is embedded in a larger energetic framework containing a massless component that is capable of bearing energy (as well as momentum in the relativistic case). Imposition of conservation and relativity then results, in the nonrelativistic case, in the conservation of mass and in the frame-invariance of massless energy; and, in the relativistic case, in the rules for transforming massless energy and momentum between frames. Third, a force framework for handling continuously interacting particles is established, wherein Newton’s second law is derived on the basis of relativity and a staccato model of motion-change. Finally, in light of the derivation, we elucidate the structure of mechanics by classifying the principles and assumptions that have been employed according to their explanatory role, distinguishing between symmetry principles and other types of principles (such as compositional principles) that are needed to build up the theoretical edifice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Sect. 5.3.1 for further details.

  2. See Sect. 5.3.1 for background on this shift.

  3. The principles that are employed, and results obtained, in each step are summarized in Tables 1 and 2 (pages 22 and 23).

  4. The mass of a body is here taken as a measure of substance from which a body is composed. In particular, no connection between mass and inertia (degree of resistance to force) is implied. The mass is assumed to be independent of the body’s state of motion, and hence frame-independent.

  5. For simplicity, this energy-additivity is taken as given here, but is in fact a manifestation of the compositional symmetry of associativity (see Sect. 5.2).

  6. We assume here that isolated bodies move at constant velocity.

  7. Although the indicated collision is a premise of the following argument, it can be traced to more primitive symmetry requirements: (a) The possibility of post-collisional motion of at least one body along the y-axis (vertical) can be traced to the requirement of continuity together with the fact that both grazing and head-on collisions are possible. (b) The fact that the post-collisional velocities must then be equal and opposite can be traced to the requirement that relatively-rotated reference frames are physically equivalent and the requirement that the same initial conditions lead to the same final conditions. Specifically, suppose that, as viewed in frame S, one particle post-collisionally travels along the positive y-axis, but the other not along the negative y-axis. Then an observer in a reference frame (\(\widetilde{S}\)) rotated about the z-axis (perpendicular to plane of collision, and passing through the midpoint of the particles’ initial positions) of S by \(\pi\) would see a collision with the same initial positions and velocities, but with one of the post-collisional velocities along the negative y-axis and the other not along the positive y-axis. That is, the same initial positions and initial velocities would lead to different post-collisional velocities for observers in S and \(\widetilde{S}\). This inconsistency can be avoided if the post-collisional velocities are along the positive and negative y-axes. Moreover, the same requirements imply that the post-collisional speeds of the two particles are equal. (c) The fact that, additionally, the post-collisional speeds coincide with the pre-collisional speeds then follows from the assumptions that (i) relatively-rotated reference frames are physically equivalent, and (ii) the time-reversed version of an elastic collision (viz. a collision that asymptotically conserves the total scalar quantity of motion) is also possible.

  8. That the mass of the composite is equal to the sum \(m_1 + m_2\) can either be assumed, or derived from the compositional symmetry of associativity (see Sect. 5.2).

  9. By definition, massless energy refers to any form of energy other than the two forms—namely, rest energy and kinetic energy—that are explicitly associated with a massive body.

  10. In Sect. 4.2, we discuss a derivation of nonrelativistic kinetic energy due to Maimon in which the frame-invariance of massless energy is implicitly assumed.

  11. Considering the motion of a body under the influence of a sequence of discrete impulses, between which the particle moves inertially, as a way of deducing results concerning the motion of the body when under the influence of a corresponding continuous force is a tactic employed extensively by Huygens, Newton, and others (see, for example, Ref. [2], where it is noted that “From Newton to Laplace, impulses were usually regarded as more fundamental, and continuous forces were assumed to be equivalent, in their observable effects, to a very rapid succession of impulses”). The specific argument given here is inspired by the derivation given in §2.1 of Ref. [2]

  12. In Ref. [2], this is referred to as the secular principle.

  13. See, for instance, [10, p. 901], [11, p. 60]. See also the discussion of Newtonian principles given in [12, Ch. 10] due to Poincaré (§8) and Painlevé (§9); and also [2, §6–7].

  14. In Sect. 4.5, we discuss an argument due to Einstein [13] which purports to show that \(b_0 = 0\).

  15. As described in Sect. 4.3, this fact is used as an axiom in the derivations of relativistic energy and momentum due to both Ehlers et al. [15] and to Lalan [16].

  16. Einstein alludes to the arbitrariness that is involved in extending ‘force = mass \(\times\) acceleration’ to the relativistic setting in [17, §10].

  17. Specifically, \(\mathbf {F} = \gamma ^3 m \mathbf {a}_\parallel + \gamma m \mathbf {a}_\perp\), while \(\mathbf {f} = \mathbf {a}_\parallel + \mathbf {a}_\perp\). Thus, for a particle of given mass, the velocity \(\mathbf {u}\) must be given in order to convert \(\mathbf {F}\) to \(\mathbf {f}\) or \(\mathbf {f}\) to \(\mathbf {F}\).

  18. See [20, 21] for illuminating discussions. Buridan’s ‘The impetus theory of projectile motion’ (from ‘Questions on the Eight Books of the Physics of Aristotle’) is available in [22] (see particularly p. 275).

  19. Buridan speculates that, if such resistance were entirely absent, a body would continue its motion indefinitely, and that such a condition might obtain with heavenly bodies.

  20. For details of the broader context of Bernoulli’s submission, see [7], Chapter 7. Bernoulli’s alternative derivations are discussed in Chapter 8.

  21. See http://www.physics.stackexchange.com/questions/535/

  22. See, for example, Ref. [26], Chapter 9

  23. The classification given here is extracted from [29]. The full classification described therein contains additional types of principle which are not required in the present discussion.

  24. For example, using Galilean relativity, one can explain what happens in an elastic head-on collision of equal bodies moving at unequal speeds \(u_1, u_2\) in terms of what happens when those some bodies collide at equal speeds \((u_1 + u_2)/2\). See also footnote 31.

  25. The first principle acts as a constraint on which start- and end-states can be dynamically connected; the second as a constraint on allowable paths connecting given initial and final configurations; and the third as a constraint on allowable quantum numbers (‘old’ quantum theory) or on possible multiparticle states (‘new’ quantum theory).

  26. For example, in the case of conservation of energy, the transformation under consideration is time evolution of the system; the ‘object’ transformed is the physical state of the system; and the equivalence relation between states is that they ‘possess’ the same total energy. The conservation principle thus posits that time evolution is a symmetry transformation of physical states with respect to this equivalence relation.

  27. More precisely, on the assumption that h is differentiable at a point, one can show [32] that \(h(a, b) = f^{-1}(f(a) + f(b))\), where f is a continuous, monotonic function. Hence, if one regraduates the masses \(m_i\) via f, so that \(\mu _i \equiv f(m_i)\), then \(\mu = \mu _1 + \mu _2\) is the total regraduated mass of the system of two bodies. However, since f is monotonic, one can just as well quantify the ‘amount of matter’ via the \(\mu _i\) rather than the \(m_i\). Hence, without loss of generality, one can say that mass is additive. The same line of argument applies to any scalar quantity, such as kinetic energy, associated with the bodies, provided that one has clear physical ground for believing that the total quantity for a system of bodies is a function of the quantities associated with each of the bodies.

  28. See, for instance, Ref. [33], Chapter 1. The core assumptions here are: (i) the resultant of two parallel forces has magnitude equal to the sum of the magnitudes of these forces, and points in the same direction; (ii) the resultant of a number of forces is commutative and associative; (iii) the resultant of two forces is rotationally covariant; (iv) the resultant of two equal forces varies continuously with the angle between these forces.

  29. In Principles II 36 [34], Descartes asserts: “there is a fixed and determined quantity of [motion] ...always the same in the universe as a whole even though there may at times be more or less motion in certain of its individual parts”, and that “when one part of matter moves twice as fast as another twice as large, there is as much motion in the smaller as in the larger”, roughly interpreted as the assertion that \(\sum _i m_i u_i\) is the conserved quantity, where m is a measure of the ‘size’ of a body.

  30. Descartes’ conservation principle was insufficient to account for collisional behaviour. Lacking another principle of similar scope capable of rectifying this insufficiency, Descartes introduced other considerations in a rather ad hoc manner. The defects of the resultant laws of collision were readily apparent. For example, Leibniz showed these laws to be inconsistent with the requirement of continuity [35, pp. 290–291]. Nevertheless, these laws were a spur to development of the correct laws.

  31. Huygens’ laws of collisions can be be divided into two cases: (i) For equal bodies in head-on collision (whether elastic or not), all collisions involving bodies with unequal incident speeds follows via relativity from the case of equal incident speeds, the behaviour in this latter case being taken as axiomatic. (ii) For unequal bodies in head-on elastic collision, the additional assumption of the asymptotic conservation of total scalar quantity of motion, where the quantity of motion is a function of speed, and an auxiliary assumption (if one mass undergoes a change, so must the other) implies that the relative speed of the two masses is the same before and after the collision. Proof sketch: in any such a collision, there is a Galilean frame of reference in which the speed of one body does not change (comparing the initial and final states), only its direction of motion. Hence, its quantity of motion does not change. But, asymptotic conservation of total quantity of motion then implies that the speed of the other body also does not change. But if the direction of one mass changes, so must the other (by the auxiliary assumption). Hence, relative speed in this chosen frame is same before and after. But relative speed is frame-independent. Therefore, irrespective of the (inertial) frame in which the collision is viewed, the relative speed is unchanged. For details, see [23, pp. 313–317] and also [36, §9.4].

  32. Huygens’ law of conservation of relative speed of two bodies in head-on elastic collision (see footnote 31) implies that the conserved quantity of motion cannot be mv (as can be seen by considering a body of mass \(m < M\) striking a body of mass M initially at rest). Furthermore, appealing to Galileo’s law of free fall and Torricelli’s principle (that the centre of gravity of a system of interacting bodies cannot rise), Huygens showed that the conserved quantity of motion is, in fact, \(mv^2\).

  33. Newton (amongst others) asserted that atoms were hard bodies that collide completely inelastically [38, pp. 4–5]. Hence the fundamental importance of formulating laws applicable to inelastic collisions.

  34. Although Leibniz championed the conservation of vis viva, a compelling account of the ‘missing’ quantity of motion at the stillpoint of an elastic collision, or at the end-point of an inelastic collision, was lacking. As a consequence, scalar conservation principles were marginalized. For example, in textbooks through to the end of the eighteenth century, elastic collisions were handled using a situation-specific law (Huygens’ conservation of the masses’ relative speed—see Footnote 31), rather than the asymptotic conservation of vis viva—see [7] (Appendix) and [8].

  35. Some attempts were made to justify the mathematical principle of momentum conservation in terms of the law of the lever. See, for example, [39], and [35, pp. 203–206].

  36. See Ref. [2] for a detailed historical investigation into these derivations.

  37. We note that this implies that the (nonrelativistic) kinetic theory of gases is inconsistent—insofar as ‘heat’ is regarded as a form of massless energy, it is frame-invariant, and so cannot be represented by the kinetic energy of a set of particles, which is not frame-invariant.

  38. We give here the some of the relevant quotes from [44]: “The conserved quantities of classical mechanics are Noether charges only because the classical equations of motion are what they are. But whether or not the classical equations of motion hold is something that needs to be established...”. And: “Given what the equations of motion are, and that they hold where they do, it is indeed necessary that the conservation laws hold, but that’s just a conditional necessity. The connection between the symmetries of the equations of motion and conservation laws is shown by Noether’s theorem. That these are the correct equations of motion, however, is a completely different matter.”

  39. The assumptions underlying the least-action approach to nonrelativistic particle mechanics can be broken down as follows: (i) the (configuration-space) trajectory, x(t), of a particle system between times \(t_1, t_2\) has an associated action S[x(t)]; (ii) the actual trajectory between given configurations at times \(t_1, t_2\) is one that extremizes S[x(t)]; (iii) the action is given by the time integral of a function, L, of x(t) and a finite number of temporal derivatives thereof; (iv) the function L has the form \(L = T - V\), where TV are the kinetic and potential energies of the system. Of these assumptions, the first three can be posited independently from Newton’s equations of motion. However, the common view is that the fourth\(L = T - V\)—arises through a transformation of Newton’s equations of motion via d’Alembert’s principle (a more direct approach is given in [45]). Although it is possible to use fundamental symmetries (homogeneity of space and time, isotropy of space, and Galilean invariance) to show that L is proportional to T for a single isolated particle [46, §4]; and, further, to use compositional symmetries to show that \(L = \sum _i T_i\) for a set of noninteracting particles, we are not aware of a derivation of \(L = T - V\) that avoids presuming Newton’s equations of motion.

References

  1. Wigner, E.P.: The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Commun. Pure Appl. Math. 13, 1 (1960)

    ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Darrigol, O.: Deducing Newton’s second law from relativity principles: a forgotten history. Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00407-019-00230-2

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Schütz, J.R.: Prinzip der absoluten erhaltung der energie, Nachr. v. d. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Math.-Phys. Kl. 2, 110 (1897)

  4. Laue, M.: Zur Dynamik der Relativitätstheorie. Ann. Phys. 35, 524 (1911)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Giulini, D.: Laue’s theorem revisited: energy-momentum tensors, symmetries, and the habitat of globally conserved quantities. Int. J. Geom. Methods Modern Phys. 15, 1850182 (2018)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Ohanian, H.C.: Did Einstein prove \(E = mc^2\)? Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 40, 167 (2009)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Iltis, C.M.: The controversy over living force: Leibniz to d’Alembert. University of Wisconsin, Madison (1967). Ph.D. thesis

    Google Scholar 

  8. Iltis, C.M.: D’Alembert and the vis viva controversy. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 1, 135 (1970)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Iltis, C.M.: Leibniz and the vis viva controversy. Isis 62, 21 (1971)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Simon, H.: Axioms of Newtonian mechanics. Philos. Mag. 38, 888 (1947)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Desloge, E.A.: Classical Mechanics, vol. 1. Wiley, New York (1982)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Dugas, R.: History of Mechanics. Dover Publications, Mineola (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Einstein, A.: Elementary derivation of the equivalence of mass and energy. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 41, 223 (1935)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Einstein, A.: Does the inertia of a body depend upon its energy content? Ann. Phys. 18, 639 (1905)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ehlers, J., Rindler, W., Penrose, R.: Energy conservation as the basis of relativistic mechanics II. Am. J. Phys. 33, 995 (1965)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Lalan, M.V.: Sur une définition axiomatique de l’impulsion et de l’énergie. C. R. Acad. Sci. 198, 1211 (1934)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Einstein, A.: On the electrodynamics of moving bodies. Ann. Phys. 17 (1905)

  18. Planck, M.: Das Prinzip der Relativität und die Grundgleichungen der Mechanik, Verhandlungen Deutsche Physikalische Gesellschaft 8, 136 (1906), English translation available at https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Translation:The_Principle_of_Relativity_and_the_Fundamental_Equations_of_Mechanics. Accessed 22 Nov 2019

  19. Tolman, R.C.: Non-Newtonian mechanics, the mass of a moving body. Philos. Mag. 23, 375 (1912)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Graney, C.M.: Mass, speed, direction: John Buridan’s 14th century concept of momentum. Phys. Teacher 51, 411 (2013)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  21. Clagett, M.: The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison (1961)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Grant, E. (ed.): A Source Book in Medieval Science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1974)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Mach, E.: The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development, 4th edn. Open Court Pub. Co., Chicago (1919)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Desloge, E.A.: Conservation laws for classical and relativistic collisions, I. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 15, 349 (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Desloge, E.A.: Conservation laws for classical and relativistic collisions, II. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 15, 357 (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Sahoo, P.K., Kannappan, P.: Introduction to Functional Equations. CRC Press, Boca Raton (2011)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Arzeliès, H.: Relativistic Point Dynamics. Pergamon Press, Oxford (1971)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Sonego, S., Pin, M.: Deriving relativistic momentum and energy. Eur. J. Phys. 26, 33 (2005)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Goyal, P.: On the explanatory role of physical principles (in preparation)

  30. Goyal, P.: Information-geometric reconstruction of quantum theory. Phys. Rev. A 78, 052120 (2008)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Goyal, P.: Origin of the correspondence rules of quantum theory (2010). arXiv:0910.2444

  32. Aczél, J.: Lectures on Functional Equations and their Application. Academic Press, New York (1966)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Aczél, J., Dhombres, J.: Functional equations in several variables. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1989)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Descartes, R.: Principles of Philosophy. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Westfall, R.S.: Force in Newton’s Physics: The Science of Dynamics in the Seventeenth Century. Science History Publications, Cambridge (1971)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. Barbour, J.B.: The Discovery of Dynamics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Leibniz, G.W.: A brief demonstration of a notable error of Descartes and others concerning a natural law, Acta eruditorum, 161 (1686), English translation, with supplements, in Philosophical papers and letters, 2nd edition, ed. L. E. Loemker, pp. 296–302

  38. Scott, W.L.: The Conflict Between Atomism and Conservation Theory 1644 to 1960. Macdonald, London (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  39. Wren, C.: Lex naturae de collisione corporum. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. 3, 867 (1669)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Huygens, C.: Regles du mouvement dans la recontre des corps. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. 4, 925 (1669)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Huygens, C.: Regles du mouvement dans la recontre des corps. J. Scavans 19 (1669)

  42. Wallis, J.: A summary account of the general laws of motion. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. 3, 864 (1669)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Kuhn, T.S.: Energy conservation as an example of simultaneous discovery. In: Kuhn, T.S. (ed.) The Essential Tension. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Wolff, J.: Are conservation laws metaphysically necessary? Philos. Sci. 8, 898 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  45. Beers, B.L.: Geometric nature of Lagrange’s equations. Am. J. Phys. 40, 1636 (1972)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  46. Landau, L.D., Lifshitz, E.M.: Mechanics, 3rd edn. Butterworth Heinemann, Oxford (2000)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  47. Goyal, P., Knuth, K.H., Skilling, J.: Origin of complex quantum amplitudes and Feynman’s rules. Phys. Rev. A 81, 022109 (2010)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  48. Goyal, P.: Informational approach to the quantum symmetrization postulate. New J. Phys. 17, 013043 (2015)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  49. Khiari, C.: Newton’s laws of motion revisited: some epistemological and didactic problems. Lat. Am. J. Phys. Educ. 5 (2011)

  50. Papachristou, C.J.: Foundations of Newtonian dynamics: an axiomatic approach for the thinking student. Nausivios Chora 4, 153 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  51. Herrmann, F., Pohlig, M., Schwarze, H.: The Karlsruhe physics course: mechanics (2019)

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am most grateful to Jennifer Coopersmith, Olivier Darrigol, Yiton Fu, PierGianLuca Porta Mana, Carolyn Merchant, Jill North, Costas Papachristou, Sebastiano Sonego, and Marius Stan for discussion and/or supportive feedback. I would particularly like to thank Olivier Darrigol for reading several versions of the paper, for pointing out historical omissions, and making important suggestions. I would also like to thank the anonymous referee for several valuable suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philip Goyal.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Solution of Functional Equations

Solution of Functional Equations

In this appendix, the functional equations needed in the derivation of the energy and momentum of bodies are solved. If possible, we transform the functional equation of interest into a standard functional equation. For interest, we sometimes provide more than one possible method of solution. In each case, certain mathematical conditions must be satisfied by the unknown function in order for a solution to be obtained.

1.1 Solution of \(f(u + v) + f(u - v) = 2f(\sqrt{u^2 + v^2})\)

We present two different solution methods for Eq. (1), one that transforms it into Jensen’s functional equation, the other a direct solution by removing one degree of freedom.

1.1.1 Solution by Transformation into Jensen’s Functional Equation

Using the substitution \(k(w^2) = f(w)\), Eq. (1) becomes

$$\begin{aligned} k\left( [u^2 + v^2] + 2uv\right) + k\left( [u^2 + v^2] - 2uv\right) = 2k(u^2 + v^2). \end{aligned}$$
(A1)

Setting \(x = u^2 + v^2\),  \(y = 2uv\), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} k(x + y) + k(x - y) = 2k(x), \end{aligned}$$
(A2)

which is Jensen’s equation, with xy independently variable within \(x>0, y>0\). If k is continuous, this equation, under the stated conditions, has general solution \(k(z) = az + b\). As k is continuous whenever f is continuous,

$$\begin{aligned} f(v) = av^2 + b \end{aligned}$$
(A3)

is the general solution of Eq. (1) under the condition that f is continuous.

1.1.2 Direct Solution by Removal of One Degree of Freedom

Alternatively, one can directly solve Eq. (1) by removing one degree of freedom, albeit at the cost of the stronger regularity condition that f is analytic. Setting \(u = v\) in Eq. (1) yields

$$\begin{aligned} f(2u) + f(0) = 2f(\sqrt{2}u). \end{aligned}$$
(A4)

If f is differentiable, then, for \(n \ge 1\),

$$\begin{aligned} 2^n f^{(n)}(2u) = 2^{1 + n/2} \, f(\sqrt{2} u). \end{aligned}$$
(A5)

This yields \(f^{(n)}(0) = 0\) whenever \(n \ne 2\). Hence, if f is analytic,

$$\begin{aligned} f(x) = av^2 + b. \end{aligned}$$
(A6)

1.2 Solution of \(g(v + u) - g(v - u) = 2g( \sqrt{u^2 + v^2}) \cdot v / \sqrt{u^2 + v^2}\)

Solution of Eq. (6) is most readily obtained by removing one degree of freedom by setting \(v = u\). Thence,

$$\begin{aligned} g(2u) - g(0) = \sqrt{2}\,g(\sqrt{2} u). \end{aligned}$$
(A7)

Setting \(u = 0\) fixes \(g(0) = 0\). If g is differentiable, then, for \(n \ge 1\),

$$\begin{aligned} 2^n g^{(n)} (2u) = 2^{(n+1)/2} \, g^{(n)}(\sqrt{2} u). \end{aligned}$$
(A8)

For \(n \ge 2\), this yields \(g^{(n)}(0) = 0\). Thus, if g is analytic,

$$\begin{aligned} g(u) = au. \end{aligned}$$
(A9)

1.3 Solution of \(\widetilde{F}(x) + \widetilde{F}(y) = 2\widetilde{F}((x+y)/2)\)

Equation (34), with \(x = \gamma (u \oplus -v)\) and \(y = \gamma (u \oplus v)\), has the form of Jensen’s equation, but it is not immediately apparent that xy are independent in some region. To see that this is so, it is helpful to express uv in terms of rapidities:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} u&= c \tanh \phi _1 \\ v&= c \tanh \phi _2. \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(A10)

Then \(u \oplus v = c\tanh (\phi _1 + \phi _2)\), so that

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} \gamma (u \oplus v)&= \tilde{\gamma }(\phi _1 + \phi _2) \\ \gamma (u \oplus -v)&= \tilde{\gamma }(\phi _1 - \phi _2), \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(A11)

where \(\tilde{\gamma }(\phi ) \equiv (1 - \tanh ^2\phi )^{-1/2}\).

Now, \(u > 0\) and \(|v| < c\), so that \(\phi _1 > 0\) and \(\phi _2\) is free. Consequently, \((\phi _1 + \phi _2)\) and \((\phi _1 - \phi _2)\) can be independently chosen. Further, since \(\tilde{\gamma }\) is monotonic, \(x = \tilde{\gamma }(\phi _1 + \phi _2)\) and \(y = \tilde{\gamma }(\phi _1 - \phi _2)\) are independent in some region. Therefore, Eq. (34) has the solution \(\widetilde{F}(x) = a + bx\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goyal, P. Derivation of Classical Mechanics in an Energetic Framework via Conservation and Relativity. Found Phys 50, 1426–1479 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00376-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00376-y

Keywords

Navigation