Skip to main content
Log in

Symmetry and Evolution in Quantum Gravity

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose an operator constraint equation for the wavefunction of the Universe that admits genuine evolution. While the corresponding classical theory is equivalent to the canonical decomposition of General Relativity, the quantum theory contains an evolution equation distinct from standard Wheeler–DeWitt cosmology. Furthermore, the local symmetry principle—and corresponding observables—of the theory have a direct interpretation in terms of a conventional gauge theory, where the gauge symmetry group is that of spatial conformal diffeomorphisms (that preserve the spatial volume of the Universe). The global evolution is in terms of an arbitrary parameter that serves only as an unobservable label for successive states of the Universe. Our proposal follows unambiguously from a suggestion of York whereby the independently specifiable initial data in the action principle of General Relativity is given by a conformal geometry and the spatial average of the York time on the spacelike hypersurfaces that bound the variation. Remarkably, such a variational principle uniquely selects the form of the constraints of the theory so that we can establish a precise notion of both symmetry and evolution in quantum gravity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The first recorded discussion of the problem of time was at the Stevens Relativity Meetings in 1958. There Dirac gave a talk on quantizing GR. The Bergmann letter follows on from that discussion. Thanks to Dean Rickles for this information.

  2. The list of references given here is not intended to be comprehensive. Readers are encouraged to consult the classic review [3] and a modern update [4] for a more detailed and wide–ranging catalogue of approaches to the Problem of Time. For our purposes, we feel that it is best to treat the ‘Problem of Time’ as an entirely separate issue to the ‘Problem of the Arrow of Time’. However, for an interesting exploration of a possible connections between the two problems see [810].

  3. The technical steps for achieving this were largely developed in [33, 34].

  4. Moncrief’s statement is closely related to the analysis of the classical Hamiltonian constraints given in [4144]

  5. Of course, one could alternatively formulate one’s methodology solely in terms of these new structures but we will not do so here.

  6. Because we are speaking about the properties of the action evaluated along curves on \({\mathcal {A}}\), which are insensitive to the internal structure of individual points on \({\mathcal {A}}\), these symmetries correspond to traditional global symmetries.

  7. Note that this is a stronger requirement then requiring that the variation of that degree of freedom on the endpoints of the variation is free, as suggested in [33].

  8. This list is not intend to be exhaustive, but rather cover all cases of physical interest.

  9. In Sect. 5, we illustrate how General Relativity can be cast into a gauge theory of this kind where the symmetry group is that of the volume preserving conformal diffeomorphisms.

  10. A related argument leading to the same conclusion is given in [42].

  11. Specifically, we are referring to the part of the best-matching procedure involved with spatial relationalism. For details on best matching see [51, 63] or [53].

  12. If \({\mathcal {A}}_\text {e}\) is thought of as a fiber bundle, where the \(\theta ^\alpha \)-directions are fibers over \({\mathcal {A}}\), then \(D\) defines a section of this bundle. We will see that, upon phase space reduction with free variation, this reduces to a covariant derivative on \({\mathcal {A}}\), as in Yang–Mills gauge theory.

  13. In other gauges, the explicit expression for the conserved charged can be obtained locally on phase space by isolating the canonical variable conjugate to the constraint \(C^\alpha = 0\) using local Darboux coordinates. The different expressions for the conserved charge in different gauges are related by the canonical transformation generated by (19). They represent non-standard representations of the original ontology of the theory.

  14. This additional requirement refines the motivations given in [33] for what was referred to as a “free endpoint variation”, despite being a more restrictive requirement than standard free endpoint variation. This explains our terminology “condition for free variation” since our “free variation” is indeed distinct from standard “free endpoint variation”. For more details surrounding these issues, see [4, 53, 63].

  15. Here we again note that, with our prescription, the Dirac quantization methodology can be substituted for a number of more rigorous modern approaches to the quantization of gauge theories provided our classification of degrees of freedom and constraints is preserved. See §3.2.2 for references.

  16. This is, for example, why ghost fields have no external legs.

  17. Here we note, once more, that there are well known formal issues with Dirac quantization that render such a Hilbert space—strictly speaking—not well defined. In a fully rigorous application of relational quantisation to a reparametrization invariant system more powerful techniques, such as group averaging [66, 67], would need to be used. Such modifications would not imply any difference in the basic structure of our arguments.

  18. A full treatment of spatial diffeomorphisms would require large diffeomorphisms, adding complications that don’t affect our main argument. For simplicity, we will restrict our discussion to infinitesimal diffeomorphisms.

  19. That the constraints (78) and (80) close only when the variations are free is a result of only considering infinitesimal, and not large, diffeomorphisms.

  20. Note that, in the quantum theory, taking \(P\), which takes values in \(\mathbb R\), as the independently specifiable degree of freedom instead of \(V_g\), which takes values in \(\mathbb R^+\), avoids the issue of having to deal with an operator valued in \(\mathbb R^+\).

  21. Uniqueness depends on the value of the cosmological constant and the matter content of the theory. For details, see [79, 80].

  22. Note that, by adding a boundary term to the extended ADM action, we can express \(\bar{\pi }_0\) as the configuration variable with \(\bar{\phi }_0\) as its conjugate momentum. This justifies \(\bar{\phi }_0\approx 0\) as the free variation condition of \(P\).

  23. In the case with no cosmological constant and Higgs mass, this theory can be shown to obey a form of dynamical similarity, as shown in [82], which may address some of these problems.

  24. Note: this can change the uniqueness properties of these solutions [83] but not the existence of solutions in the spatially closed case.

References

  1. Bergman, P.G.: Letter to P. A. M. Dirac, (Oct 9th 1959)

  2. DeWitt, B.: Quantum theory of gravity. I. The canonical theory. Phys. Rev. 160, 1113–1148 (1967)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Isham, C.: Canonical quantum gravity and the problem of time. Arxiv preprint gr-qc (1992). http://arxiv.org/abs/grqc/9210011

  4. Anderson, E.: The problem of time in quantum gravity. Ann. Phys. 524, 757–786 (2012)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Dirac, P.A.M.: The theory of gravitation in hamiltonian form. Proc. R Soc. Lond. Ser. A Math. Phys. Sci. 246, 333–343 (1958)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Arnowitt, R., Deser, S., Misner, C.W.: Canonical variables for general relativity. Phys. Rev. 117, 1595–1602 (1960)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Moncrief, V.: How solvable is (2 + 1)-dimensional Einstein gravity? J. Math. Phys. 31, 2978 (1990)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  8. Kiefer, C., Zeh, H.: Arrow of time in a recollapsing quantum universe. Phys. Rev. D 51(8), 4145 (1995)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. Kiefer, C.: Quantum Gravity. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Kiefer, C.: Can the arrow of time be understood from quantum cosmology? In: The Arrows of Time, pp. 191–203. Springer, Heidelberg (2012)

  11. Bombelli, L., Lee, J., Meyer, D., Sorkin, R.D.: Space-time as a causal set. Phys. Rev. Lett. 59(5), 521–524 (1987)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Dowker, F.: Causal sets and the deep structure of spacetime. In: Ashtekar, A. (ed.) 100 Years of Relativity, Space-Time Structure: Einstein and Beyond, pp. 445–464. World Press Scientific, Singapore (2005)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Henson, J.: The causal set approach to quantum gravity. arXiv, preprint gr-qc/0601121 (2006)

  14. Isham, C., Butterfield, J.: Some possible roles for topos theory in quantum theory and quantum gravity. Found. Phys. 30(10), 1707–1735 (2000)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Isham, C.: Some reflections on the status of conventional quantum theory when applied to quantum gravity. In: The Future of the Theoretical Physics and Cosmology (Cambridge, 2002): Celebrating Stephen Hawking’s 60th Birthday, pp. 384–408 (2002)

  16. Hardy, L.: Towards quantum gravity: a framework for probabilistic theories with non-fixed causal structure. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 40(12), 3081 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Rovelli, C.: Quantum mechanics without time: a model. Phys. Rev. D 42, 2638–2646 (1990)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  18. Rovelli, C.: Time in quantum gravity: an hypothesis. Phys. Rev. D 43, 442 (1991)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  19. Rovelli, C.: Partial observables. Phys. Rev. D 65, 124013 (2002)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Dittrich, B.: Partial and complete observables for canonical general relativity. Class. Quant. Gravity 23, 6155 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Dittrich, B.: Partial and complete observables for hamiltonian constrained systems. General Relat. Gravit. 39, 1891 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  22. Dittrich, B., Thiemann, T.: Testing the master constraint programme for loop quantum gravity: I. General framework. Class. Quant. Gravity 23, 1025–1065 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. Thiemann, T.: The phoenix project: master constraint programme for loop quantum gravity. Class. Quant. Gravity 23, 2211 (2006)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Thiemann, T.: Modern Canonical Quantum General Relativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2007)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Husain, V., Pawlowski, T.: Time and a physical Hamiltonian for quantum gravity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 108, 141301 (2012). arXiv:1108.1145[gr-qc]

    Google Scholar 

  26. Giesel, K., Thiemann, T.: Scalar material reference systems and loop quantum gravity. arXiv:1206.3807[gr-qc]

  27. Brown, J.D., Kuchar, K.V.: Dust as a standard of space and time in canonical quantum gravity. Phys. Rev. D 51 (1995) 5600–5629. arXiv:gr-qc/9409001[gr-qc]

  28. Isham, C., Kuchar, K.: Representations of space-time diffeomorphisms 2. Canonical geometrodynamcis. Ann. Phys. 164, 316 (1985)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. Loll, R.: Discrete lorentzian quantum gravity. Nucl. Phys. B Proc. Suppl. 94(1), 96–107 (2001)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  30. Ambjørn, J., Jurkiewicz, J., Loll, R.: Dynamically triangulating lorentzian quantum gravity. Nucl. Phys. B 610(1), 347–382 (2001)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  31. York, J.: Boundary terms in the action principles of general relativity. Found. Phys. 16(3), 249–257 (1986)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  32. Gryb, S., Thébault, K.: The role of time in relational quantum theories. Found. Phys. 42, 1210–1238 (2012)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  33. Anderson, E., Barbour, J., Foster, B.Z., Kelleher, B., O’Murchadha, N.: The physical gravitational degrees of freedom. Class. Quant. Gravity 22, 1795–1802 (2005). arXiv:gr-qc/0407104

    Google Scholar 

  34. Gomes, H., Gryb, S., Koslowski, T.: Einstein gravity as a 3D conformally invariant theory. Class. Quant. Gravity 28, 045005 (2011). arXiv:1010.2481[gr-qc]

  35. Brown, J.D., York, J.W.J.: Jacobi’s action and the recovery of time in general relativity. Phys. Rev. D 40, 3312–3318 (1989)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  36. Henneaux, M., Teitelboim, C.: The cosmological constant and general covariance. Phys. Lett. B 222, 195–199 (1989)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  37. Unruh, W.G.: A unimodular theory of canonical quantum gravity. Phys. Rev. D 40, 1048 (1989)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  38. Unruh, W.G., Wald, R.M.: Time and the interpretation of canonical quantum gravity. Phys. Rev. D40, 2598 (1989)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  39. Smolin, L.: The quantization of unimodular gravity and the cosmological constant problem. arXiv:0904.4841[hep-th]

  40. Kuchar, K.V.: Does an unspecified cosmological constant solve the problem of time in quantum gravity? Phys. Rev. D 43, 3332–3344 (1991)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  41. Barbour, J.B.: The Timelessness of quantum gravity. 1: The evidence from the classical theory. Class. Quant. Gravity 11, 2853–2873 (1994)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  42. Barbour, J., Foster, B.Z.: Constraints and gauge transformations: Dirac’s theorem is not always valid. (Aug., 2008). arXiv:0808.1223[gr-qc]

  43. Pons, J., Salisbury, D., Sundermeyer, K.A.: Observables in classical canonical gravity: folklore demystified. J. Phys. A Math. General 222, 12018 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Pitts, J.B.: Change in hamiltonian general relativity from the lack of a time-like killing vector field. (Oct., 2013). http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/10094/

  45. Kuchař, K.: The Problem of Time in Quantum Geometrodynamics, pp. 169–195. Oxford University Press, New York (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Kuchar̆, K.: The problem of time in canonical quantization of relativistic systems. In: Ashtekar, A., Stachel, J. (eds.) Conceptual Problems of Quantum Gravity, p. 141. Birkhauser, Boston (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Kuchař, K.V.: Time and interpretations of quantum gravity. In: Kunstatter G., Vincent D., Williams J. (eds.) Proceedings of the Fourth Canadian Conference on General Relativity and Relativistic Astrophysics, held 16–18 May, 1991 at University of Winnipeg, pp. 211–314. World Scientific, Singapore (1992)

  48. Fatibene, L., Francaviglia, M., Mercadante, S.: Noether symmetries and covariant conservation laws in classical, relativistic and quantum physics. arXiv:1001.2886[gr-qc]

  49. Gomes, H., Koslowski, T.: The link between general relativity and shape dynamics. Class. Quant. Gravity 29, 075009 (2012). arXiv:1101.5974[gr-qc]

  50. Poincaré, H.: Science et Hypothèse. Ernest Flammarion, Paris (1902)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  51. Barbour, J.B., Bertotti, B.: Mach’s principle and the structure of dynamical theories. Proc. R. Soc. A 382(1783), 295–306 (1982)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  52. Barbour, J.: Dynamics of pure shape, relativity and the problem of time. In: Decoherence and Entropy in Complex Systems (Proceedings of the Conference DICE, Piombino 2002, Elze H.-T. (ed.)). Springer Lecture Notes in Physics. Springer, New York (2003)

  53. Gryb, S.B.: A definition of background Independence. Class. Quant. Gravity. 27, 215018 (2010). arXiv:1003.1973[gr-qc]

  54. Dirac, P.A.M.: Lectures on Quantum Mechanics. Dover Publications, Yeshivea University, New York (1964)

  55. Henneaux, M., Teitelboim, C.: Quantization of Gauge Systems. University Press, Princeton (1992)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  56. Vytheeswaran, A.: Gauge unfixing in second class constrained systems. Ann. Phys. 236, 297–324 (1994)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  57. York, J.J.W.: Gravitational degrees of freedom and the initial-value problem. Phys. Rev. Lett. 26, 1656–1658 (1971)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  58. York, J.J.W.: Conformally invariant orthogonal decomposition of symmetric tensors on Riemannian manifolds and the initial value problem of general relativity. J. Math. Phys. 14, 456–464 (1973)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  59. York, J.J.W.: Role of conformal three geometry in the dynamics of gravitation. Phys. Rev. Lett. 28, 1082–1085 (1972)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  60. Cook, G.B.: Initial data for numerical relativity. Living Rev. Relativ. 3(5), (2000). http://www.livingreviews.org/lrr-2000-5

  61. Mukhanov, V.F., Feldman, H., Brandenberger, R.H.: Theory of cosmological perturbations. Part 1. Classical perturbations. Part 2. Quantum theory of perturbations. Part 3. Extensions. Phys. Rept. 215, 203–333 (1992)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  62. Barbour, J.: Shape dynamics. An introduction. arXiv:1105.0183

  63. Barbour, J.: Scale-invariant gravity: particle dynamics. Class. Quant. Gravity 20, 1543–1570 (2003). arXiv:gr-qc/0211021

  64. Isham, C., Kakas, A.: A group theoretical approach to the canonical quantisation of gravity. I. Construction of the canonical group. Class. Quant. Gravity 1(6), 621 (1984)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  65. Isham, C., Kakas, A.: A group theoretical approach to the canonical quantisation of gravity. II. Unitary representations of the canonical group. Class. Quant. Gravity 1(6), 633 (1984)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  66. Giulini, D., Marolf, D.: On the generality of refined algebraic quantization. Class. Quant. Gravity 16, 2479–2488 (1999)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  67. Giulini, D., Marolf, D.: A uniqueness theorem for constraint quantization. Class. Quant. Gravity 16, 2489–2505 (1999)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  68. Kuchař, K.: General relativity: dynamics without symmetry. J. Math. Phys. 22, 2640 (1981)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  69. Kuchar, K.V.: Canonical quantum gravity. arXiv:gr-qc/9304012[gr-qc]

  70. Torre, C.: Gravitational observables and local symmetries. Phys. Rev. D Part. Fields 48(6), R2373 (1993)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  71. Hájícek, P.: Choice of gauge in quantum gravity. Nucl. Phys. B Proc. Suppl. 80, 1213 (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  72. Anderson, E.: Relational quadrilateralland. II. Analogues of isospin and hypercharge. arXiv:1202.4187[gr-qc]

  73. Gomes, H.deA.: Gauge theory in Riem: classical. Accepted to J. Math. Phys. arXiv:0807.4405[gr-qc]

  74. Arnowitt, R.L., Deser, S., Misner, C.W.: The dynamics of general relativity. In Witten, L. (ed.) Gravitation: An Introduction to Current Research, chap. 7, pp. 227–265. arXiv:gr-qc/0405109.

  75. Teitelboim, C.: How commutators of constraints reflect the space-time structure. Ann. Phys. 79, 542–557 (1973)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  76. Thiemann, T.: Modern canonical quantum general relativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2007). arXiv:gr-qc/0110034[gr-qc]

  77. Isham, C.J.: Canonical quantum gravity and the problem of time. arXiv:gr-qc/9210011

  78. Dirac, P.A.M.: Fixation of coordinates in the Hamiltonian theory of gravitation. Phys. Rev. 114, 924–930 (1959)

    Article  ADS  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  79. Gomes, H.: The coupling of shape dynamics to matter. J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 360, 012058 (2012). arXiv:1112.0374[gr-qc]

  80. Gomes, H.: Breaking the uniqueness of the shape dynamics Hamiltonian. arXiv:1201.3969[gr-qc]

  81. O’Murchadha, N., York, J.J.W.: Existence and uniqueness of solutions of the hamiltonian constraint of general relativity on compact manifolds. J. Math. Phys. 4, 1551–1557 (1973)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  82. Barbour, J., Koslowski, T., Mercati, F.: The solution to the problem of time in shape dynamics. arXiv:1302.6264[gr-qc]

  83. Gomes, H., Koslowski, T.: Coupling shape dynamics to matter gives spacetime. General Relat. Gravity 44 (2012) 1539–1553. arXiv:1110.3837[gr-qc]

  84. Barbour, J., Lostaglio, M., Mercati, F.: Scale anomaly as the origin of time. arXiv:1301.6173[gr-qc]

  85. Strominger, A.: Inflation and the dS/CFT correspondence. JHEP 0111, 049 (2001). arXiv:hep-th/0110087[hep-th]

  86. McFadden, P., Skenderis, K.: The holographic universe. J. Phys. Conf. Ser. 222, 012007 (2010). arXiv:1001.2007[hep-th]

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Edward Anderson, Julian Barbour, Brian Pitts, Henrique Gomes, Tom Pashby, Hans Westman and Ken Wharton for comments on the draft, and Igor Khavkine for useful discussions. SG would like to acknowledge support from and NSERC PDF grant, for travel support from Renate Loll, and for the hospitality of Utrecht and Radboud Universities. KT would like to acknowledge support from the Alexander von Humboldt foundation and the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sean Gryb.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gryb, S., Thébaault, K. Symmetry and Evolution in Quantum Gravity. Found Phys 44, 305–348 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-014-9789-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-014-9789-x

Keywords

Navigation