Advertisement

Foundations of Physics

, Volume 43, Issue 4, pp 548–567 | Cite as

Classical Levels, Russellian Monism and the Implicate Order

  • William Seager
Article

Abstract

Reception of the Bohm-Hiley interpretation of quantum mechanics has a curiously Janus faced quality. On the one hand, it is frequently derided as a conservative throwback to outdated classical patterns of thought. On the other hand, it is equally often taken to task for encouraging a wild quantum mysticism, often regarded as anti-scientific. I will argue that there are reasons for this reception, but that a proper appreciation of the dual scientific and philosophical aspects of the view reveals a powerful and extremely interesting metaphysical view of the world. This view is akin to that of Russellian Monism, in which the empirical world studied by science is restricted to relational features that stand in need of some background intrinsic properties to ground their reality. This allows for a theory that can embrace a world which exhibits a reasonable and plausible sort of emergence (especially of domains that fall under classical concepts) while also making room for distinctive and scientifically intransigent properties such as consciousness.

Keywords

Bohm Hiley Monism Quantum potential Implicate order Active information 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to express my thanks to the organizers of the Helsinki conference in honour of Basil Hiley’s 75th birthday, and indeed to Professor Hiley himself, especially for his longstanding efforts to integrate philosophical thinking into the investigation of quantum physics. My thanks also to the journal’s anonymous referees whose challenging and insightful comments helped me to clarify the views expressed here.

References

  1. 1.
    Albert, D.: Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1992) Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Anderson, P.: More is different. Science 177(4047), 393–396 (1972) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Barbour, J.: The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2000) Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Batterman, R.: The Devil in the Details: Asymptotic Reasoning in Explanation, Reduction and Emergence. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2002) zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Bedau, M.: Weak emergence. In: Tomberlin, J. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives 11: Mind, Causation, and World, pp. 375–399. Blackwell, Oxford (1997) Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Bohm, D.: Wholeness and the Implicate Order. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1980) Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Boyd, R.: Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson, R. (ed.) Species: New Interdisciplinary Studies, pp. 141–185. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1999) Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Brock, W.: The Norton History of Chemistry. W.H. Norton & Co., New York (1993) Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Carroll, S.: The laws underlying the physics of everyday life are completely understood. http://blogs.discovermagazine.com/cosmicvariance/2010/09/23/the-laws-underlying-the-physics-of-everyday-life-are-completely-understood/ (2010)
  10. 10.
    Chalmers, D.: The conscious mind. In: Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1996) Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    de Gosson, M., Hiley, B.: Zeno paradox for Bohmian trajectories: the unfolding of the metatron. arXiv:1010.2622 (2010)
  12. 12.
    Eddington, A.: The Nature of the Physical World. Macmillan & Co., New York (1928) Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Eliasmith, C.: Is the brain analog or digital? Cogn. Sci. Q. 1(2), 147–170 (2000) Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Frescura, F., Hiley, B.: Algebras, quantum theory and pre-space. Rev. Bras. Fís. 49–86 (1984). Vol. Especial Os 70 anos de Mario Schonberg Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Hagan, S., Hameroff, S.R., et al.: Quantum computation in brain microtubules: decoherence and biological feasibility. Phys. Rev. E 65(6), 061901 (2002) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Hameroff, S., Penrose, R.: Conscious events as orchestrated space-time selections. J. Conscious. Stud. 3, 36–53 (1996) Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Hameroff, S., Powell, J.: The conscious connection: a psycho-physical bridge between brain and Pan-experiential quantum geometry. In: Skrbina, D. (ed.) Mind That Abides: Panpsychism in the New Millennium, pp. 109–127. Benjamins, Amsterdam (2009) Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Henson, S., Constantino, R., et al.: Lattice effects observed in chaotic dynamics of experimental populations. Science 294, 602–605 (2001) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Hiley, B.: Mind and matter: aspects of the implicate order described through algebra. In: Pribram, K., King, J. (eds.) Learning as Self-Organisation, pp. 569–586. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale (1996) Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Hiley, B.: Active information and teleportation. In: Greenberger, D., Reiter, W., Zeilinger, A. (eds.) Epistemological and Experimental Perspectives on Quantum Physics. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht (1999) Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Hiley, B.: Quantum theory, the implicate order and the self. http://www.bbk.ac.uk/tpru/BasilHiley/Hiley-QT_IOandSelf.pdf
  22. 22.
    Hiley, B.: From the Heisenberg picture to Bohm: a new perspective on active information and its relation to Shannon information. In: Khrennikov, A. (ed.) Quantum Theory: Reconsideration of Foundations, pp. 141–162. Växjö University Press, Växjö (2002) Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Hiley, B.: Particles, fields and observers. In: Baltimore, D., Dulbecco, R., Jacob, F., Levi-Montalcini, R. (eds.) Frontiers of Life, vol. 1, pp. 89–106. Academic Press, New York (2002) Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    Hiley, B., Callaghan, R.E.: Delayed-choice experiments and the Bohm approach. Phys. Scr. 74(3), 336–348 (2006) MathSciNetADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    Hiley, B., Callaghan, R.E.: What is erased in the quantum erasure? Found. Phys. 36, 1869–1883 (2006) MathSciNetADSzbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. 26.
    Hiley, B., Pylkkänen, P.: Can mind affect matter via active information? Mind Matter 3(2), 7–27 (2005) Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Holland, P.: The Quantum Theory of Motion: An Account of the de Broglie-Bohm Causal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. 28.
    Holland, J.: Emergence: From Chaos to Order. Addison-Wesley, Reading (1998) zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  29. 29.
    Jaynes, E.T.: Quantum beats. In: Barut, A. (ed.) Foundations of Radiation Theory and Quantum Electrodynamics, pp. 37–43. Plenum, New York (1980) Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Joos, E., Zeh, H.D., et al.: Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory, 2nd edn. Springer, Berlin (2003) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Kocsis, S., et al.: Observing the average trajectories of single photons in a two-slit interferometer. Science 332, 1170–1173 (2011) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. 32.
    Ladyman, J., Ross, D., et al.: Everything Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007) Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Langton, R.: Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1998) Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Langton, R., Lewis, D.: Defining “intrinsic”. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 58, 333–345 (2001) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. 35.
    Laughlin, R.: A Different Universe. Basic Books, New York (2005) Google Scholar
  36. 36.
    Leibniz, G.W.: Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1710/1951). Farrer A. (ed.), Huggard, E. (trans.) Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    Lockwood, M.: Mind, Brain and the Quantum. Blackwell, Oxford (1989) Google Scholar
  38. 38.
    McLaughlin, B.: The rise and fall of British emergentism. In: Beckermann, A., Flohr, H., Kim, J. (eds.) Emergence or Reduction, pp. 49–93. De Gruyter, Berlin (1992) Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Mermin, D.: What is quantum mechanics trying to tell us? Am. J. Phys. 66(9), 753–767 (1998) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Morowitz, H.: The Emergence of Everything: How the World Became Complex. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2002) Google Scholar
  41. 41.
    Newman, M.: Mr. Russell’s causal theory of perception. Mind 37, 137–148 (1928) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    Nielsen, M., Chuang, I.: Quantum Computation and Quantum Information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000) zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  43. 43.
    O’Connor, T.: Emergent properties. Am. Philos. Q., Monogr. Ser. 31, 91–104 (1994) Google Scholar
  44. 44.
    O’Connor, T., Wong, H.Y.: The metaphysics of emergence. Noûs 39, 658–678 (2005) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. 45.
    Popper, K., Eccles, J.: The Self and Its Brain. Springer, New York (1977) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 46.
    Pullman, B.: The Atom in the History of Human Thought. Oxford University Press, New York (1998) Google Scholar
  47. 47.
    Pylkännen, P.: Mind, Matter and the Implicate Order. Springer, Berlin (2007) Google Scholar
  48. 48.
    Rumelhart, D., McClelland, J., et al.: Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, vol. 1. MIT Press, Cambridge (1986) Google Scholar
  49. 49.
    Russell, B.: The Analysis of Mind. George Allen & Unwin, London (1921) Google Scholar
  50. 50.
    Russell, B.: An Outline of Philosophy. George Allen & Unwin, London (1927) Google Scholar
  51. 51.
    Russell, B.: Mind and matter. In: Portraits from Memory, pp. 145–165. Spokesman, Nottingham (1956) Google Scholar
  52. 52.
    Scully, M., Drühl, K.: Quantum eraser: a proposed photon correlation experiment concerning observation and “delayed choice” in quantum mechanics. Phys. Rev. A 25, 2208–2213 (1982) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. 53.
    Scully, M., Englert, B., et al.: Quantum optical tests of complementarity. Nature 351, 111–116 (1991) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. 54.
    Seager, W.: The ‘intrinsic nature’ argument for panpsychism. J. Conscious. Stud. 13, 129–145 (2006) (Reprinted in Freeman A. (ed.) Consciousness and Its Place in Nature, Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2006.) Google Scholar
  55. 55.
    Silberstein, M., McGeever, J.: The search for ontological emergence. Philos. Q. 49, 182–200 (1999) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. 56.
    Stapp, H.: A quantum theory of the mind-brain interface. In: Mind, Matter and Quantum Mechanics, pp. 145–172. Springer, Berlin (1993) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. 57.
    Stenger, V.: The myth of quantum consciousness. Humanist. 53, 13–15 (1993) Google Scholar
  58. 58.
    Stoljar, D.: Two conceptions of the physical. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 62, 253–281 (2001) CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. 59.
    Stubenberg, L.: Neutral monism. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008). The Metaphysics Research Lab, fall 2008 ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/neutral-monism Google Scholar
  60. 60.
    Tegmark, M.: Importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes. Phys. Rev. E, Stat. Nonlinear Soft Matter Phys. 61(4), 4194–4206 (2000) ADSCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. 61.
    Vigier, J.P., Dewdney, C., et al.: Causal particle trajectories and the interpretation of quantum mechanics. In: Hiley, B., Peat, D. (eds.) Quantum Implications: Essays in Honor of David Bohm, pp. 169–204. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1987) Google Scholar
  62. 62.
    Wheeler, J.: The “past” and the “delayed choice” double-slit experiment. In: Marlow, A. (ed.) Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 9–48. Academic Press, New York (1978) CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of TorontoTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations