Skip to main content
Log in

On the Relationship Between Modelling Practices and Interpretive Stances in Quantum Mechanics

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The purpose of this article is to establish a connection between modelling practices and interpretive approaches in quantum mechanics, taking as a starting point the literature on scientific representation. Different types of modalities (epistemic, practical, conceptual and natural) play different roles in scientific representation. I postulate that the way theoretical structures are interpreted in this respect affects the way models are constructed. In quantum mechanics, this would be the case in particular of initial conditions and observables. I examine two formulations of quantum mechanics, the standard wave-function formulation and the consistent histories formulation, and show that they correspond to opposite stances, which confirms my approach. Finally, I examine possible strategies for deciding between these stances.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is at least the case for the theories of physics, which are the main focus of this paper.

  2. This is consistent with the idea that epistemic possibilities are a subset of conceptual possibilities, which are a subset of logical possibilities, which, in this case, would correspond to the set of all mathematical structures.

  3. Note that I am not trying to capture the process of model construction, but the final product. Presumably, scientists start from epistemic and practical constraints and then use conceptual inferences to construct an appropriate model. In retrospect, the constraints from which they started can be seen as restrictions on the space of available conceptual possibilities. Relations of necessity can be approached inferentially, or semantically, and the two approaches are complementary. Also note that this is a simplification, because models do not always strictly satisfy the laws of a theory, for example when approximations are used, and they often incorporate domain-specific postulates. However, I will neglect these complications here.

  4. They can be replaced by final conditions in the case of retrodictions, or by any relevant input concerning the properties of the system at a particular time. In the following, I will only consider initial conditions, but my analyses can easily be transposed.

  5. This observation cannot be generalised to unbounded systems. A counterexample (that I owe to an anonymous reviewer) is scattering theory, where the Hamiltonian is variable while initial conditions and observables are fixed. This could entail that the conclusions of this article are limited to the representation of some systems, notably bound systems. Further analyses beyond the scope of this paper would be required to address this potential limitation. However, the representation of bound systems remains canonical in physics, in particular when it comes to interpretive issues, and I hope that the analyses provided in what follows are still valuable as a demonstration of the fruitfulness of the methodological approach presented in this article.

  6. I should note that another option consists in fixing a privileged observable at the conceptual level, and not at the practical or epistemic level. This option corresponds to Bohmian mechanics, which specifies that the positions of particles have definite values, whatever the model. In this case, the right observable could be considered a matter of natural (or even metaphysical) necessity, because it has nothing to do with the identification of the target. Note, however, that it is debatable whether fixing a “privileged basis” such as position at the conceptual level amounts to fixing observables: a distinct notion of observable that is independent from this privileged basis can be seen as supervening on the relation between a system and its environment.

  7. The fact that the Hilbert space and algebra of observables are fixed, and potentially reflect a focus from the user of the model on particular properties of interest, could let us think that representation is perspectival in all cases. However, it is perspectival only in a weak sense, because of the selective interests of users, but properties of interest could still be objective. One can reasonably assume that the Hilbert space could be completed with new properties without affecting the initial content of the model. Fixing an observable makes the model perspectival in a stronger sense, insofar as observables are associated with the anthropocentric notion of measurement, and affect the content of the model.

  8. Two more stances could have been considered: fixing everything, or fixing nothing at the basic level of abstraction (and perhaps still others considering unbounded systems: see footnote 5). However, they are less interesting because they do not specify a priority between observable and initial conditions, so I will leave them out.

  9. This perspectivist stance could be compared to perspectivist positions in epistemology, such as Giere (2010b) and Massimi (2018)’s perspectival realism. The notion of perspective involved here is arguably more local, since it concerns a focus on some properties for a concrete target of representation, while perspectival realism puts emphasis on relativity to a conceptual scheme, a theoretical lexicon or epistemic norms of justification at a more general level. Nevertheless, there could be interesting connections between the two, notably because one of the motivations of perspectival realism is to account for the successful use of incompatible models to represent a single target system. There is no place to explore these connections here.

  10. I am grateful to a reviewer for raising this objection.

References

  • Arrasmith, A., Cincio, L., Sornborger, A. T., Zurek, W. H., & Coles, P. J. (2019). Variational consistent histories as a hybrid algorithm for quantum foundations. Nature Communications, 10(1), 3438. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-019-11417-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailer-Jones, D. (2013). Scientific models in philosophy of science (Vol. 43). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. (2004). Against measurement. In J. Bell (Ed.), Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics (pp. 213–231). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Belot, G. (2012). Quantum states for primitive ontologists. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(1), 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, B. (2017). There is a special problem of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 970–981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brun, T. A., & Hartle, J. B. (1999). Classical dynamics of the quantum harmonic chain. Physical Review D, 60(12), 123503. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.60.123503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C., & Jonathan, C. (2006). “There is no special problem about scientific representation”. Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de La Ciencia, 21(1): 67–85.

  • Carlip, S. (2001). Quantum gravity: A progress report. Reports on Progress in Physics, 64(8), 885–942. https://doi.org/10.1088/0034-4885/64/8/301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2007). Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 74(1), 48–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, D. (2016). The consistent histories approach to loop quantum cosmology. International Journal of Modern Physics D, 25(08), 1642009. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0218271816420098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowker, F., & Kent, A. (1996). On the consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics. Journal of Statistical Physics, 82(5–6), 1575–1646. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02183396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elby, A. (1992). Should we explain the EPR correlations causally? Philosophy of Science, 59(1), 16–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Hoefer, C. (2007). Probability in GRW theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38(2), 371–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1999). Science without laws. Science and Its conceptual foundations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2010a). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 269–281. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9506-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2010b). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1968). Utterer’s meaning, sentence-meaning, and word-meaning. Foundations of Language, 4(3), 225–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, R. (2003). Consistent quantum theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, R. (2019). “The consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics.” In Edward, N. Z. (eds) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/qm-consistent-histories/.

  • Healey, R. (2012). Quantum theory: A pragmatist approach. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(4), 729–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, C. (2015). Re-Inflating the conception of scientific representation. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(1), 41–59. https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2014.979671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massimi, M. (2018). Perspectival modeling. Philosophy of Science, 85(3), 335–359. https://doi.org/10.1086/697745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (1995). Three measurement problems. Topoi, 14(1), 7–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okon, E., & Sudarsky, D. (2014). On the consistency of the consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics. Foundations of Physics, 44(1), 19–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pusey, M. F., Barrett, J., & Rudolph, T. (2012). On the reality of the quantum state. Nature Physics, 8(6), 475–478. https://doi.org/10.1038/nphys2309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J., & Pexton, M. (2013). Reassessing Woodward’s account of explanation: Regularities, counterfactuals, and noncausal explanations. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 613–624. https://doi.org/10.1086/673899.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2003). Scientific representation: Against similarity and isomorphism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17(3), 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). an inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 767–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1972). What’s wrong with the received view on the structure of scientific theories? Philosophy of Science, 39(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2007). Quantum probability from subjective likelihood: Improving on Deutsch’s proof of the probability rule. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B, 38(2), 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations=Philosophische Untersuchungen. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Quentin Ruyant.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ruyant, Q. On the Relationship Between Modelling Practices and Interpretive Stances in Quantum Mechanics. Found Sci 27, 387–405 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09774-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09774-x

Keywords

Navigation