Foundations of Chemistry

, Volume 16, Issue 2, pp 149–163 | Cite as

Pure possibilities and some striking scientific discoveries

Article

Abstract

Regardless or independent of any actuality or actualization and exempt from spatiotemporal and causal conditions, each individual possibility is pure. Actualism excludes the existence of individual pure possibilities, altogether or at least as existing independently of actual reality. In this paper, I demonstrate, on the grounds of my possibilist metaphysics—panenmentalism—how some of the most fascinating scientific discoveries in chemistry could not have been accomplished without relying on pure possibilities and the ways in which they relate to each other (for instance, in theoretical models). The discoveries are the following: Dan Shechtman’s discovery of quasicrystals; Linus Pauling’s alpha helix; the discovery of F. Sherwood Rowland and Mario J. Molina concerning the destruction of the atmospheric ozone layer; and Neil Bartlett’s noble gas compounds. On the grounds of the analysis of these cases, actualism must fail, whereas panenmentalism gains support.

Keywords

Scientific discoveries Actualism Excluding possibilities Possibilism Panenmentalism Models 

References

  1. Armstrong, D.M.: Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Atiyah, M.: Address of the president. Not. Rec. R. Soc. Lond. 49(1), 141–151 (1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bennett, K.: Two axes of actualism. Philos. Rev. 114, 297–326 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bennett, K.: Proxy “Actualism”. Philos. Stud. 129, 263–294 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cocchiarella, N.B.: Formal Ontology and Conceptual Realism. Springer, Dordrecht (2007)Google Scholar
  6. Contessa, G.: Modal truthmakers and two varieties of actualism. Synthese 174, 341–353 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Freund, M.A., Cocchiarella, N.B.: Modal Logic: An Introduction to Its Syntax and Semantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)Google Scholar
  8. Gilead, A.: Saving Possibilities: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology, vol. 80. Rodopi—Value Inquiry Book Series, Amsterdam & Atlanta (1999)Google Scholar
  9. Gilead, A.: Singularity and Other Possibilities: Panenmentalist Novelties, vol. 139. Rodopi—Value Inquiry Book Series, Amsterdam & New York (2003)Google Scholar
  10. Gilead, A.: Necessity and Truthful Fictions: Panenmentalist Observations, vol. 202. Rodopi—Value Inquiry Book Series, Amsterdam & New York (2009)Google Scholar
  11. Gilead, A.: Actualist fallacies, from fax technology to lunar journeys. Philos. Lit. 34(1), 173–187 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gilead, A.: The Privacy of the Psychical, vol. 233. Rodopi—Value Inquiry Book Series, Amsterdam & New York (2011)Google Scholar
  13. Gilead, A.: Shechtman’s three question marks: Impossibility, possibility, and quasicrystals. Found. Chem. (2012) doi:10.1007/s10698-012-9156-y
  14. Gillespie, R.J., Hargittai, I.: The VSEPR Model of Molecular Geometry. Allyn & Bacon, Boston (1991)Google Scholar
  15. Hargittai, I.: Candid Science III: More Conversations with Famous Chemists, Hargittai, M. (ed). Imperial College Press, London (2003)Google Scholar
  16. Hargittai, I.: Structures beyond crystals. J. Mol. Str. 976, 81–86 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hargittai, I.: Drive and Curiosity: What Fuels the Passions for Science. Prometheus Books, Amherst (2011a)Google Scholar
  18. Hargittai, I.: Geometry and models in chemistry. Str. Chem. 22(3), 3–10 (2011b)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hargittai, I.: Dan Shechtman’s quasicrystal discovery in perspective. Israel J. Chem. 51, 1–9 (2011c). doi:10.1002/ijch.201100137 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hellman, G.: Mathematics Without Numbers: Towards a Modal-Structural Interpretation. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1989)Google Scholar
  21. McEvoy, M.: The epistemological status of computer-assisted proofs. Philos. Math. 16, 374–387 (2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. McMichael, A., Zalta, E.N.: An alternative theory of nonexistent objects. J. Philos. Logic 9(3), 297–313 (1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Menzel, Ch.: Actualism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition), Zalta, E. N. (ed.), URL=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/actualism/ (2011)
  24. Nelson, M., Zalta, E.N.: Bennett and “proxy actualism”. Philos. Stud. 142, 277–291 (2009)Google Scholar
  25. Solzhenitsyn, A.: Cancer Ward. Trans. Bethell, N., Burg, D. Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, New York (2001 [1968])Google Scholar
  26. Stalnaker, R.: Assertion revisited: on the interpretation of two-dimensional modal semantic. Philos. Stud. 118, 299–322 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Stalnaker, R.: Mere Possibilities: Metaphysical Foundations of Modal Semantics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2012)Google Scholar
  28. Stein, H.: Logos, logic, and logistiké. Minn. Stud. Philos. Sci. 11, 238–259 (1988)Google Scholar
  29. Vetter, B.: Recent work: modality without possible worlds. Analysis 71(4), 742–754 (2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Weyl, H.: Consistency in mathematics. Rice Inst. Pamphlet 16, 245–265 (1929)Google Scholar
  31. Woodward, R.: The things that aren’t actually there. Philos. Stud. 152, 155–166 (2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Yost, D., Kaye, A.L.: An attempt to prepare a chloride or fluoride of xenon. J. Am. Chem. Soc. 55, 3890–3892 (1933)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Zalta, E.: Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics. Reidel, Dordrecht (1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of HaifaHaifaIsrael

Personalised recommendations