Foundations of Chemistry

, Volume 14, Issue 3, pp 205–219 | Cite as

Prigogine and the many voices of nature

Article

Abstract

Ilya Prigogine was not a systematic author: his ideas, covering a wide arch of areas, are dispersed in his many writings. In particular, his philosophical thought has to be reconstructed mainly on the basis of his works in collaboration with Isabelle Stengers: La Nouvelle Alliance (1979), Order out of Chaos (1984), and Entre le Temps et l’Éternité (1988). In this paper I undertake that reconstruction in order to argue that Prigogine’s position, when read in the light of Putnam’s internalist realism, can be characterized as an ontological pluralism. The main aim of this work is to show the striking parallelism between the philosophical views of Prigogine and Stengers and those of Hilary Putnam in Reason, Truth and History (1981). This task will lead me to critically review Prigogine’s general scientific program: the attempt to establish the foundations of objective irreversibility.

Keywords

Prigogine Putnam Ontological pluralism Irreversibility 

References

  1. Antoniou, I., Prigogine, I.: Intrinsic irreversibility and integrability of dynamics. Phys. A 192, 443–464 (1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bachelard, G.: Le Pluralisme Cohérent de la Chimie Moderne. J. Vrin, Paris (1932)Google Scholar
  3. Batterman, R.: Randomness and probability in dynamical theories: on the proposals of the Prigogine school. Philos. Sci. 58, 241–263 (1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bensaude-Vincent, B., Stengers, I.: Histoire de la Chimie. Paris: La Découverte (English trans). A History of Chemistry. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1993)Google Scholar
  5. Bishop, R.: Nonequilibrium statistical mechanics Brussels–Austin style. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Sci. 35, 1–30 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bohm, A., Gadella, M.: Dirac Kets, Gamow Vectors and Gel’fand Triplets: The Rigged Hilbert Space Formulation of Quantum Mechanics. Springer Lecture Notes in Physics, vol. 348. Springer, New York (1989)Google Scholar
  7. Castagnino, M., Gadella, M., Lombardi, O.: Time’s arrow and irreversibility in time-asymmetric quantum mechanics. Int. Stud. Philos. Sci. 19, 223–243 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Castagnino, M., Gadella, M., Lombardi, O.: Time-reversal, irreversibility and arrow of time in quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 36, 407–426 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Castagnino, M., Lombardi, O.: Self-induced decoherence: a new approach. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 35, 73–107 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Castagnino, M., Lombardi, O.: Self-induced decoherence and the classical limit of quantum mechanics. Philos. Sci. 72, 764–776 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Castagnino, M., Lombardi, O., Lara, L.: The global arrow of time as a geometrical property of the universe. Found. Phys. 33, 877–912 (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Earley, J.E.: Introduction: a life for future. Stud. Philos. IV, 99–105 (2004)Google Scholar
  13. Eddington, A.: The Nature of the Physical World. Macmillan, New York (1928)Google Scholar
  14. Gadella, M.: Derivation of Gamow vectors for resonances in cut-off potentials. Lett. Math. Phys. 41, 279–290 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Heisenberg, W.: Physics and Beyond: Encounters and Conversations. Harper and Row, New York (1971)Google Scholar
  16. Koopman, B.O.: Hamiltonian systems and transformations in Hilbert space. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 17, 315–318 (1931)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Labarca, M., Lombardi, O.: Why orbitals do not exist? Found. Chem. 12, 149–157 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lombardi, O.: Prigogine: ciencia y realidad. Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 30, 47–75 (1998a)Google Scholar
  19. Lombardi, O.: Prigogine y la teoría del caos: una crítica filosófica. Revista de Filosofía ADEF XIII, 97–117 (1998b)Google Scholar
  20. Lombardi, O.: El fin de la omnisciencia: la respuesta de Prigogine al problema de la irreversibilidad. Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 14, 489–510 (1999a)Google Scholar
  21. Lombardi, O.: Prigogine y la reducción en ciencias. Cadernos de História e Filosofia da Ciência 9, 123–145 (1999b)Google Scholar
  22. Lombardi, O.: La interpretación de la irreversibilidad: Prigogine versus Gibbs. Diálogos XXXV, 37–56 (2000)Google Scholar
  23. Lombardi, O.: Determinism, internalism and objectivity. In: Atmanspacher, H., Bishop, R. (eds.) Between Chance and Choice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Determinism, pp. 75–87. Imprint-Academic, Thorverton (2002)Google Scholar
  24. Lombardi, O.: El problema de la ergodicidad en mecánica estadística. Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 35, 3–41 (2003)Google Scholar
  25. Lombardi, O., Labarca, M.: Los enfoques de Boltzmann y de Gibbs frente al problema de la irreversibilidad. Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 37, 39–81 (2005a)Google Scholar
  26. Lombardi, O., Labarca, M.: The ontological autonomy of the chemical world. Found. Chem. 7, 125–148 (2005b)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lombardi, O., Labarca, M.: The ontological autonomy of the chemical world: a response to Needham. Found. Chem. 8, 81–92 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Merleau-Ponty, M.: Le philosophe et la sociologie. In: Merleau-Ponty, M. (ed.) Éloge de la Philosophie, pp. 97–122. Gallimard, Paris (1953)Google Scholar
  29. Misra, B., Prigogine, I.: Time, probability and dynamics. In: Horton, C.W., Reichl, L.E., Szebehely, V.G. (eds.) Proceedings of the Workshop on Long-Time Predictions in Nonlinear Conservative Dynamical Systems, pp. 21–43. Wiley, New York (1981)Google Scholar
  30. Misra, B., Prigogine, I.: Irreversibility and nonlocality. Lett. Math. Phys. 7, 421–429 (1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Misra, B., Prigogine, I., Courbage, M.: From deterministic dynamics to probabilistic descriptions. Phys. A 98, 1–26 (1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Nicolis, G., Prigogine, I.: Exploring Complexity: An Introduction. W. H. Freeman, New York (1989)Google Scholar
  33. Pérez Ransanz, A.R.: Kuhn y el Cambio Científico. Fondo de Cultura Económica, México (1999)Google Scholar
  34. Prigogine, I.: Science, reason and passion. Leonardo 29, 39–42 (1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Prigogine, I., Stengers, I.: La Nouvelle Alliance. Gallimard, Paris (1979)Google Scholar
  36. Prigogine, I., Stengers, I.: Order Out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature. Bantam Books, New York (1984)Google Scholar
  37. Prigogine, I., Stengers, I.: Entre le Temps et l’Éternité. Fayard, Paris (1988)Google Scholar
  38. Putnam, H.: Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Putnam, H.: The Many Faces of Realism. Open Court, La Salle (1987)Google Scholar
  40. Schuster, H.G.: Deterministic Chaos. VCH, Weinheim (1984)Google Scholar
  41. Sklar, L.: Physics and Chance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Torretti, R.: Scientific realism and scientific practice. In: Agazzi, E., Pauri, M. (eds.) The Reality of the Unobservable: Observability, Unobservability and their Impact on the Issue of Scientific Realism, pp. 112–122. Kluwer, Dordrecht (2000)Google Scholar
  43. Torretti, R.: Manuel Kant. Estudios sobre los Fundamentos de la Filosofía Crítica. Editorial de la Universidad Diego Portales, Santiago de Chile (2005)Google Scholar
  44. Torretti, R.: Objectivity: a Kantian perspective. In: Massimi, M. (ed.) Kant and Philosophy of Science Today, pp. 81–94. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)Google Scholar
  45. Vihalemm, R.: A. Whitehead’s metaphysical ontology and I. Prigogine’s scientific ontology: from a point of view of a theoretical conception of science. Problemos 71, 78–90 (2007)Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.CONICETUniversity of Buenos AiresBuenos AiresArgentina

Personalised recommendations