Skip to main content
Log in

The Right to Feel Comfortable: Implicit Bias and the Moral Potential of Discomfort

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An increasingly popular view in scholarly literature and public debate on implicit biases holds that there is progressive moral potential in the discomfort that liberals and egalitarians feel when they realize they harbor implicit biases. The strong voices among such discomfort advocates believe we have a moral and political duty to confront people with their biases even though we risk making them uncomfortable. Only a few voices have called attention to the aversive effects of discomfort. Such discomfort skeptics warn that, because people often react negatively to feeling blamed or called-out, the result of confrontational approaches is often counterproductive. To deepen this critique, I distinguish between awareness discomfort and interaction discomfort, developing a contextual approach that draws on recent research on negative affect and emotions to chart a more complete picture of the moral limits of discomfort. I argue that discomfort advocates risk overrating the moral potential of discomfort if they underestimate the extent to which context shapes the interpretation of affect and simple, raw feelings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This way of framing the debate is inspired by Daniel Kelly’s useful conceptualization of disgust advocates and skeptics (Kelly 2011).

  2. In a forthcoming paper (“Against Comfort: Political and Social Consequences of Evading Discomfort”) I defend a version of the advocate position.

  3. Some domains of the research on implicit biases are currently under scrutiny as part of the replication crisis in the social sciences. It has, for example, been questioned whether the Implicit Association Test can accurately track implicit biases on an individual level (See Kurdi and Banaji 2017 for a reply to the criticism) and to what extent implicit biases can predict discriminatory behavior (consult Brownstein et al. 2019, for a critical discussion). The foundation of the research on implicit biases, however, includes many other measures which remain robust, consult for example Jost et al. 2009 or Holroyd et al. 2017a.

  4. One notable exception is “Project Perfect”, led by Lisa Bortolotti at Birmingham University, which aims to identify when imperfect cognitions are good for us: https://www.birmingham.ac.uk/generic/perfect/index.aspx. Accessed 5 June, 2019.

  5. Implicit biases are heterogeneous (Holroyd and Sweetman 2016) and researchers continue to study to what extent agents can access (Cooley et al. 2018; Hahn and Gawronski 2019) and control (Conrey et al. 2005) their implicit biases and to what degree implicit biases differ in these respects from explicit biases. It would therefore be a mischaracterization to label implicit biases as entirely unconscious in a Freudian sense (Machery 2016). A promising alternative is to understand implicit biases as spontaneous affective states (Hahn and Gawronski 2019).

  6. In the study, a person with a distinct white or black dialect called a wrong telephone number for help. The caller explained that their car was disabled and that they needed someone to call up the nearest garage, because they had no more coins to make the call themselves. Many similar studies followed (see Dovidio and Gaertner 2004, 9–11). Other contemporary studies document how helping behavior furthers subtle forms of discrimination: “Discrimination of even the most apparently well-intentioned kind—helping members of in-group—has significant impact on those who are not part of the in-group and those who are” (Summary of this research in Banaji and Greenwald 2013, 140–143, 160–163).

  7. Other more recent studies also document how implicit biased persons display increased discomfort (anxiety, nervousness, awkwardness) when interacting with black patients (Hagiwara et al. 2017) and when instructing black learners (Jacoby-Senghor et al. 2016). In another study, subjects with white preference on the IAT showed less comfort and less friendliness when talking to a black interviewer than a white counterpart. Discomfort indicators included speech errors, speech hesitations, positioning of the rolling chair to the interviewer (McConnell and Leibold 2001). Consult summary in Dovidio and Gaertner 2010.

  8. For a pointed discussion of the relationship between testimonies and so-called scientific evidence of racial bias, see Schroer 2015.

  9. For a comprehensive literature review, consult Hahn and Gawronski 2019.

  10. It is important to note that killjoy is not only something performed intentionally. Individuals can be killjoys by merely entering a room, or more directly, by being seen as different and norm-divergent, a being whose presence disrupts the status quo (Wandel Petersen and Mølgaard Tams 2016).

  11. Both Bailey and Applebaum adhere to the “pedagogies of discomfort” (Boler 2009; Kumashiro 2002). As Shoshana Felman, one prominent representative of this tradition, argues: “[i]f teaching does not hit upon some sort of crisis…it has perhaps not been truly taught” (Felman and Laub 1991, p. 53).

  12. Zheng cites empirical studies that have identified how “high-threat” accusations of, for example, being called a racist can lead to aversive behavior like denial and resistance, negative affect, and negative evaluations (Czopp et al. 2006). Other studies confirm the same tendency, namely that pushing for an acknowledgement of guilt/blameworthiness may create a backlash (see summary in Bartlett 2009). The take-away message from these and other empirical studies on the moral potential of confrontation is, however, not straightforward (see literature review in Czopp 2019). In Czopp 2006, for example, participants who experienced discomfort also displayed a reduction in stereotypic inference and reported less prejudiced attitudes in a follow-up study. Similarly, a recent study confirms that participants who had been confronted with their biases reported that they had been reflecting more on the episode, made more attempts to suppress biased behavior, and were more motivated to be egalitarian compared to participants who were not confronted (Chaney and Sanchez 2018). These experiments support the middle position of so-called moderate discomfort advocates that I’ll discuss in the next section.

  13. There is no scholarly consensus on what qualifies as racism. For an overview of the discussions, consult Appiah 1992; Blum 2007; Levy 2017.

  14. Several philosophers have launched similar arguments against associating implicit bias with the moral character of the agent and questioned the appropriateness of blaming the agent for his or her biases (Saul 2014; Levy 2017). See also Alex Madva’s discussion of a similar group of theorists he calls “exonerators” (Madva 2018). Others argue that we cannot rely on traditional definitions of moral responsibility when it comes to implicit biases and that this calls for a revision of our traditional ideas about what moral responsibility entails (Faucher 2016; Glasgow 2016). Other discussions have focused on individual versus societal accountability (Haslanger 2015 and discussions of Haslanger’s position by Jennifer Saul and Rachel Sterken forthcoming in Disputatio 2019). For an overview of these debates, see Holroyd et al. 2017b.

  15. For example, epistemology (Diaz-Leon 2016; Rysiew 2016) and political theory (Lægaard 2016). For other insightful contextual approaches to emotions, see Eickers et al. 2017; Betz et al. 2019.

  16. A broad range of psychologists and philosophers have advocated for this thesis of “the primacy of affect”, from Antonio Damasio to the contemporary influential voice of the constructivist theory of emotion, neuropsychologist Lisa Barrett. Other pioneering researchers include Wilhelm Wundt, James A. Russel and Gerald Clore. This body of research primarily originates from cognitive and affective sciences with a focus on affect as an inner state. Another approach from cultural studies also stresses on the relational dynamics of affect. There are many differences between these two traditions but the primary point of agreement is that affect has a significant influence on human judgment and perception. For an overview of these discussions, see for example Leys 2011.

  17. Our experience of affect is part of the larger phenomenon of interoception, basically a form of inner perception. In Barrett’s words, it is the “brain’s representation of all sensations from your internal organs and tissues, the hormones in your blood, and your immune system” (Barrett 2017, p. 56).

  18. Alex Madva makes a similar point concerning the indeterminate nature of the gut feelings underlying racial biases (Madva 2019).

  19. Other moderate discomfort advocates argue that such internal motivations are not necessary for discomfort to be morally productive. Studies show that even less egalitarian individuals respond to uncomfortable confrontations with less prejudice simply to avoid being called out (Monteith et al. 2019). See also philosopher José Medina’s useful discussion of beneficial and detrimental epistemic friction (Medina 2013, chap. 1).

  20. For an overview, consult Clore and Schiller 2016.

References

  • Ahmed S (2010) Feminist killjoys (and other willful subjects). Sch Fem Online Barnard Cent Res Women 8:3

    Google Scholar 

  • Allport GW (1958) The nature of prejudice. Doubleday, Garden City

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah KA (1992) Racisms. In: Goldberg DT (ed) Anatomy of racism. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Applebaum B (2017) Comforting discomfort as complicity: white fragility and the pursuit of invulnerability. Hypatia 32:862–875. https://doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailey A (2017) Tracking privilege-preserving epistemic pushback in feminist and critical race philosophy classes. Hypatia 32:876–892. https://doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banaji MR, Greenwald AG (2013) Blindspot: hidden biases of good people. Delacorte Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett LF (2017) How emotions are made: the secret life of the brain. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett K (2009) Making good on good intentions: the critical role of motivation in reducing implicit workplace discrimination. Va Law Rev 95:1893–1972

    Google Scholar 

  • Betz N, Hoemann K, Barrett LF (2019) Words are a context for mental inference. Emotion. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo0000510

  • Bloom P (2018) Against empathy: the case for rational compassion. Vintage, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum LA (2007) “I’m not a racist, but ...”: the moral quandary of race. Cornell Univ. Press, Ithaca

  • Boler M (2009) Feeling power: emotions and education. Routledge, New York; London

  • Brownstein M, Madva A, Gawronski B (2019) Understanding implicit Bias: putting the criticism into perspective. Pac Philos Q

  • Carter E (2018) Starbucks’ diversity training won’t help unless it makes white people uncomfortable. In: The Undefeated. https://theundefeated.com/features/starbucks-diversity-training-wont-help-unless-it-makes-white-people-uncomfortable/. Accessed 8 Nov 2018

  • Chaney KE, Sanchez DT (2018) The endurance of interpersonal confrontations as a prejudice reduction strategy. Personal Soc Psychol Bull 44:418–429. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167217741344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clore GL, Schiller AJ (2016) New light on the affect-cognition connection. In: Barrett LF, Lewis M, Haviland JM (eds) Handbook of emotions, 4th edn. Guilford Press, New York, pp 532–546

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrey FR, Sherman JW, Gawronski B et al (2005) Separating multiple processes in implicit social cognition: the quad model of implicit task performance. J Pers Soc Psychol 89:469–487. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.89.4.469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooley E, Lei RF, Ellerkamp T (2018) The mixed outcomes of taking ownership for implicit racial biases. Personal Soc Psychol Bull 44:1424–1434. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167218769646

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox WTL, Devine PG (2019) Chapter 12: the prejudice habit-breaking intervention: an empowerment-based confrontation approach. In: Mallett RK, Monteith MJ (eds) Confronting Prejudice and Discrimination. Academic Press, pp 249–274

  • Czopp AM (2019) Chapter 10: the consequences of confronting prejudice. In: Mallett RK, Monteith MJ (eds) Confronting Prejudice and Discrimination. Academic Press, pp 201–221

  • Czopp AM, Monteith MJ, Mark AY (2006) Standing up for a change: reducing bias through interpersonal confrontation. J Pers Soc Psychol 90:784–803. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.90.5.784

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devine PG (1989) Stereotypes and prejudice: their automatic and controlled components. J Pers Soc Psychol 56:5–18. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.56.1.5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiAngelo R (2011) White fragility. Int J Crit Pedagogy 3:54–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Diaz-Leon E (2016) Epistemic Contextualism and conceptual ethics. In: Ichikawa J (ed) Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Contextualism

  • Dovidio JF, Gaertner SL (2004) Aversive racism. In: Advances in experimental social psychology. Elsevier Academic Press, San Diego, pp 1–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Dovidio JF, Gaertner SL (2010) Intergroup Bias. In: Handbook of Social Psychology. Wiley Online Library

  • Eddo-Lodge R (2017) Why I’m no longer talking to white people about race. The Guardian

  • Eickers G, Loaiza JR, Prinz J (2017) Embodiment, context-sensitivity, and discrete emotions: a response to moors. Psychol Inq 28:31–38. https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2017.1255492

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faucher L (2016) Revisionism and moral responsibility for implicit attitudes. In: Brownstein M, Saul J (eds) Implicit Bias and philosophy: moral responsibility, structural injustice, and ethics. Oxford University Press

  • Felman S, Laub D (1991) Testimony: crises of witnessing in literature, psychoanalysis, and history. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Festinger L, Carlsmith JM (1959) Cognitive consequences in forced compliance. J Abnorm Soc Psychol 203–210

  • Forscher PS, Mitamura C, Dix EL, Cox WTL, Devine PG (2017) Breaking the prejudice habit: mechanisms, timecourse, and longevity. J Exp Soc Psychol 72:133–146. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2017.04.009

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glasgow J (2016) Alienation and responsibility. In: Brownstein M, Saul J (eds) Implicit Bias and philosophy. Oxford University Press

  • Hagiwara N, Slatcher RB, Eggly S, Penner LA (2017) Physician racial Bias and word use during racially discordant medical interactions. Health Commun 32:401–408. https://doi.org/10.1080/10410236.2016.1138389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn A, Gawronski B (2019) Facing one’s implicit biases: from awareness to acknowledgment. J Pers Soc Psychol 116:769–794. https://doi.org/10.1037/pspi0000155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J and Lukianoff G (2015) The coddling of the American mind. The Atlantic

  • Haslanger S (2015) Distinguished lecture: social structure, narrative and explanation. Can J Philos 45:1–15. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2015.1019176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holroyd J, Scaife R, Stafford T (2017a) What is implicit bias? Philos Compass 12. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12437

  • Holroyd J, Scaife R, Stafford T (2017b) Responsibility for implicit bias. Philos Compass 12. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12410

  • Holroyd J, Sweetman J (2016) The heterogeneity of implicit Bias. In: Brownstein M, Saul J (eds) Implicit Bias and philosophy. Oxford University Press

  • Jacoby-Senghor DS, Sinclair S, Shelton JN (2016) A lesson in bias: the relationship between implicit racial bias and performance in pedagogical contexts. J Exp Soc Psychol 63:50–55. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2015.10.010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jost JT, Rudman LA, Blair IV et al (2009) The existence of implicit bias is beyond reasonable doubt: a refutation of ideological and methodological objections and executive summary of ten studies that no manager should ignore. Res Organ Behav 29:39–69. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.riob.2009.10.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2015) Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly D (2011) Yuck!: the nature and moral significance of disgust. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kumashiro KK (2002) Troubling education queer activism and anti-oppressive pedagogy. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kurdi B, Banaji MR (2017) Reports of the death of the individual difference approach to implicit social cognition may be greatly exaggerated: a commentary on Payne, Vuletich, and Lundberg. Psychol Inq 28:281–287. https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2017.1373555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurth C (2018) The anxious mind: an investigation into the varieties and virtues of anxiety. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lægaard S (2016) Contextualism in normative political theory. Oxf Res Encycl Polit. https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.87

  • Levy N (2017) Am I a racist? Implicit Bias and the ascription of racism. Philos Q 67:534–551. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqw070

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leys R (2011) The turn to affect: a critique. Crit Inq 37:434–472. https://doi.org/10.1086/659353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lukianoff G, Haidt J (2018) The coddling of the American mind: how good intentions and bad ideas are setting up a generation for failure. Penguin Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery E (2016) De-Freuding implicit attitudes. In: Saul J, Brownstein M (eds) Implicit Bias and philosophy. Oxford University Press

  • Madva A (2018) Implicit Bias, moods, and moral responsibility. Pac Philos Q 99:53–78. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madva A (2019) Social psychology, phenomenology, and the indeterminate content of unreflective racial Bias. In: Lee ES (ed) Race as phenomena: between phenomenology and philosophy of race. Rowman & Littlefield International

  • McConnell AR, Leibold JM (2001) Relations among the implicit association test, discriminatory behavior, and explicit measures of racial attitudes. J Exp Soc Psychol 37:435–442. https://doi.org/10.1006/jesp.2000.1470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medina J (2013) The epistemology of resistance, gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and resistant imaginations. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Monteith MJ, Burns MD, Hildebrand LK (2019) Chapter 11: navigating successful confrontations: what should I say and how should I say it? In: Mallett RK, Monteith MJ (eds) Confronting Prejudice and Discrimination. Academic Press, pp 225–248

  • Munch-Jurisic DM (in review) Against Comfort: Political Consequences of Evading Discomfort

  • Rankine C (2015) Citizen: an American lyric. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson J (2005) Deeper than reason: emotion and its role in literature, music, and art. Clarendon press, Oxford University press, Oxford; New York, NY

  • Rysiew P (2016) Epistemic Contextualism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, winter 2016. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University

  • Saul J (2014) Implicit Bias, stereotype threat, and women in philosophy. In: Hutchison K, Jenkins F (eds) Women in philosophy: what needs to change? Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Scaife R, Holroyd J, Stafford T, Bunge A (2009) The Effects of Moral Interactions on Implicit Racial Bias https://osf.io/awq2c/

  • Schroer JW (2015) Giving them something they can feel: on the strategy of Scientizing the phenomenology of race and racism. Knowl Cult 3:91–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Soloski A (2018) In This Play About Race, ‘People Need to Be Uncomfortable.’ N. Y. Times

  • Stephan A, Walter S (forthcoming) situated affect. In: Szanto T, Landweer H (eds) the Routledge handbook of phenomenology of emotions. Routledge, London

  • Sullivan S (2015) The physiology of sexist and racist oppression. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wandel Petersen A, Mølgaard Tams L (2016) Killjoy. https://killjoy.dk/da/Dictionary/Killjoy. Accessed 5 Jun 2019

  • Williams B (1981) Moral luck. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zembylas M (2012) Pedagogies of strategic empathy: navigating through the emotional complexities of anti-racism in higher education. Teach High Educ 17:113–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zheng R (2016) Attributability, accountability, and implicit Bias. In: Brownstein M, Saul J (eds) Implicit Bias and philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was made possible by a postdoctoral fellowship from the Carlsberg Foundation (Grant no. CF16-0580).

Many thanks for comments and suggestions for earlier versions of this paper to the reviewers at ETMP, Alex Madva, Jules Holroyd, Jennifer Saul, Sally Haslanger, Laurencia Sainz, Robin Zheng, Charlie Kurth, Thomas Brudholm and Birgitte S. Johansen, Milicent Churcher, Christopher Bennett, Rikke Andreassen, Heidi Maibom, Pedja Jurisic, and the audiences at the Work-in-progress-seminar, University of Sheffield (May 2018), the Greyzone summer school, University of Edinburgh (June 2018), the Annual Conference for the European Philosophical Society for the Study of Emotions (Pisa 2019) and the members in my research group for Criminal Justice Ethics at Roskilde University: Jesper Ryberg, Thomas Søbirk Petersen, Sebastian Holmen, Søren Sophus Wichmann, Rune Klingenberg, Frej Klem Thomsen, Kristian Kragh.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ditte Marie Munch-Jurisic.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Munch-Jurisic, D.M. The Right to Feel Comfortable: Implicit Bias and the Moral Potential of Discomfort. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 237–250 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10064-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10064-5

Keywords

Navigation