Ethics and Information Technology

, Volume 18, Issue 4, pp 299–309 | Cite as

Robots, law and the retribution gap

Original Paper

Abstract

We are living through an era of increased robotisation. Some authors have already begun to explore the impact of this robotisation on legal rules and practice. In doing so, many highlight potential liability gaps that might arise through robot misbehaviour. Although these gaps are interesting and socially significant, they do not exhaust the possible gaps that might be created by increased robotisation. In this article, I make the case for one of those alternative gaps: the retribution gap. This gap arises from a mismatch between the human desire for retribution and the absence of appropriate subjects of retributive blame. I argue for the potential existence of this gap in an era of increased robotisation; suggest that it is much harder to plug this gap than it is to plug those thus far explored in the literature; and then highlight three important social implications of this gap.

Keywords

Robotics Law Moral responsibility Liability gaps Retribution gaps 

References

  1. Alexander, L., & Ferzan, K. (2009). Crime and culpability: A theory of criminal law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Asaro, P. (2011). A body to kick and still no soul to damn: Legal perspectives on robotics. In P. Lin, K. Abney, & G. A. Bekey (Eds.), Robot ethics: The ethical and social implications of robotics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. Atran, S. (2002). In gods we trust: The evolutionary landscape of religion. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  4. Barrett, J. (2004). Why would anyone believe in God?. Walnut Creek, CA: AltaMira Press.Google Scholar
  5. Boonin, D. (2008). The problem of punishment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bostrom, N. (2012). The superintelligent will: Motivation and instrumental rationality in artificial agents. Minds and Machines, 22(2), 71–85.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bostrom, N. (2014). Superintelligence: Paths, strategies and dangers. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  8. Boyer, P. (2002). Religion explained. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
  9. Brahman, D., Kahan, D. M., & Hoffman, D. A. (2010). Some realism about punishment naturalism. University of Chicago Law Review, 77, 1531.Google Scholar
  10. Brown, D. O. (1991). Human universals. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  11. Bryant, C. (2015). Worker killed in Volkswagen robot accident. Financial Times July 1, 2015.Google Scholar
  12. Calo, R. (2015). Robotics and the lessons of cyberlaw. California Law Review, 103(3), 513–563.MathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  13. Calo, R., Kerr, I., & Froomkin, M. (Eds.). (2016). Robot law. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.Google Scholar
  14. Carlsmith, K. M., & Darley, J. M. (2008). Psychological aspects of retributive justice. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology. San Diego, CA: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  15. Chisan Hew, P. (2014). Artificial moral agents are infeasible with existing technologies. Ethics and Information Technology, 16, 197–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Duff, R. A. (2007). Answering for crime: Responsibility and liability in criminal law. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  17. Ford, M. (2015). The rise of the robots. London: Oneworld Publications.Google Scholar
  18. Gintis, H. (2011). The bounds of reason. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.MATHGoogle Scholar
  19. Gunkel, D. (2012). The machine question. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Hart, H. L. A. (1968). Punishment and responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hellstrom, T. (2013). On the moral responsibility of military drones. Ethics and Information Technology, 15, 99–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hinds, P., Roberts, T., & Jones, H. (2004). Whose job is it anyway? A study of human-robot interaction in a collaborative task. Human–Computer Interaction, 19, 151–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Jensen, K. (2010). Punishment and spite: The dark side of cooperation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 365, 2635–2650.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kaplan, J. (2015). Humans need not apply. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Kiesler, S., & Goetz, J. (2002). Mental models of robotic assistants. In Conference proceedings of CHI 2002, extended abstracts on human factors in computing systems, pp. 576–77.Google Scholar
  26. Kim, T., & Hinds, P. J. (2006). Who should i blame? Effects of autonomy and transparency on attributions in human-robot interaction. In Proceedings of RO-MAN’06. http://web.stanford.edu/~phinds/PDFs/Kim-Hinds-ROMAN.pdf. Accessed 11 Nov, 15.
  27. Kitchin, R. (2016). Thinking critically about and researching algorithms. Information, Communication and Science,. doi:10.1080/1369118X.2016.1154087.Google Scholar
  28. Kramer, M. (2011). The ethics of capital punishment. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Levy, N. (2014). Consciousness and moral responsibility. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, status and design of corporate agents. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. MacDorman, K. F. (2006). Subjective ratings of robot video clips for human likeness, familiarity, and eeriness: An exploration of the uncanny valley. In Proceedings of the ICCS/CogSci-2006: Toward social mechanisms of android science.Google Scholar
  32. MacDorman, K. F., Green, R. D., Ho, C.-C., & Koch, C. T. (2009). Too real for comfort? Uncanny responses to computer generated faces. Computers in Human Behavior, 25(3), 695–710.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. MacDorman, K. F., & Ishiguro, H. (2006). The uncanny advantage of using androids in cognitive and social science research. Interaction Studies, 7(3), 297–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Marin, A. L., Jo, D., & Lee, S. (2013). Designing robotic avatars. Are user’s impressions affected by avatar’s age? In Proceedings of the 8th ACM/IEEE international conference on humanrobot interaction, HRI, March 3–6, 2013.Google Scholar
  35. Matthias, A. (2004). The responsibility gap: Ascribing responsibility for the actions of learning automata. Ethics and Information Technology, 6(3), 175–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Matthias, A. (2011). Algorithmic moral control of war robots: Philosophical questions. Law, Innovation and Technology, 3(2), 279–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Moore, M. (1993). Justifying retributivism. Israel Law Review, 27, 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Moore, M. (1997). Placing blame: A general theory of criminal law. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  39. Muehlhauser, L., & Helm, L. (2013). The singularity and machine ethics. In A. Eden, J. Moor, J. Soraker, & E. Steinhart (Eds.), Singularity hypotheses: A scientific and philosophical assessment. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  40. Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  41. Prevost, A. M. (1992). Race and war crimes: The 1945 war-crimes trial of general Tomoyuki Yamashita. Human Rights Quarterly, 14, 303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Purves, D., Jenkins, R., & Strawser, B. (2015). Autonomous machines, moral judgment, and acting for the right reasons. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18, 851–872.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Robinson, P. H. (2013). Intuitions of justice and the utility of desert. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Robinson, P. H., & Kurzban, R. (2007). Concordance and conflict in intuitions of justice. Minnesota Law Review, 91, 1829–1892.Google Scholar
  45. Robinson, P. H., Kurzban, R., & Jones, O. D. (2007). The origins of shared intuitions of justice. Vanderbilt Law Review, 60, 1633.Google Scholar
  46. Sainato, M. (2015). Stephen Hawking, Elon Musk and Bill Gates Warn about artificial intelligence. The Observer Aug 19, 2015.Google Scholar
  47. Scherer, M. (2016). Regulating artificial intelligence systems: Risks, challenges, competencies and strategies. Harvard Journal of Law and Technology, 29(2). doi:10.2139/ssrn.2609777.
  48. Simpson, T., & Muller, V. (2016). Just wars and robots’ killings. The Philosophical Quarterly,. doi:10.1093/pq/pqv075.Google Scholar
  49. Sparrow, R. (2007). Killer robots. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 24(1), 62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Vincent, N. (2011). A structured taxonomy of responsibility concepts. In N. Vincent, I. van de Poel, & J. van den Hoven (Eds.), Moral responsibility: Beyond free will and determinism. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Walker, A. (2016). Why self driving cars should never have steering wheels. Gizmodo Feb 24, 2016. http://gizmodo.com/why-self-driving-cars-really-shouldnt-ever-have-steerin-1758292942.
  52. Yamashita, In re. (1946). 321 US 1.Google Scholar
  53. Zimmerman, M. (2011). The immorality of punishment. Peterborough: Broadview Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of LawNUI GalwayGalwayIreland

Personalised recommendations