Skip to main content
Log in

An A Priori Refutation of the Classical Pessimistic Induction

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to the Classical Pessimistic Induction (CPI), otherwise positive features like predictive and explanatory success actually cast doubt on theories that display them. After all, they negatively correlate with truth. From this historical track record, it is inferred that current best theories are probably not (even approximately) true. The CPI is often wielded against realists about science, but others like Hume (Moral philosophy. Geoffrey Sayre McCord (ed), Hackett Publishing Company, 1757), Pareto (The mind and society, vol 1. (Arthur Livingston, Trans.), Harcourt, Brace and Company, New York, 1935), and Hájek (in: Green and Williams (eds) Moore’s paradox: new essays on belief, rationality, and the first person, Oxford University Press, 2007) extend it to philosophical theories more generally. In this paper, I unveil a priori refutations that defang the CPI in all its guises. To date, treatments of this topic typically assume the following: if the historical proportion of false theories increases, then it has increasingly negative bearing against realism. I show that this assumption is false. I identify three types of problems for the CPI, each attaching to some interpretation or other. The first problem is that the CPI violates a universal adequacy condition on the confirmation relation that restricts the relationship between entailment and disconfirmation. The second problem is that the induction’s target hypotheses preclude the track record from instantiating a list of epistemically significant properties that empirical information is supposed to afford. The third problem is that it is constitutively impossible for the CPI to have random samples; this implies that even the use of randomization procedures cannot help. In sum: my refutation is novel, accessible by pure reflection, and quite general.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This nomenclature is borrowed from Stanford (2006, ch. 1.2).

  2. The CPI features with varying prominence in many discussions, including Putnam (1978), Newton-Smith (1981), Horwich (1982), Kuhn (1992), Weston (1992), Kitcher (1993), Worrall (1994), Hobbs (1994), Leplin (1984; 1997), Lipton (2000), Lewis (2001), Blackburne (2002), Lange (2002), Kukla and Walmsley (2004), Magnus and Callender (2004), Stanford (2003, 2006, ch. 1.2), Chakravartty (2007), Bird (2007, 2022, p. 232–239), Nola (2008), Magnus (2010), Papineau (2010), Roush (2010), Frost-Arnold (2011), Devitt (2010, ch. 4, 2011), Fahrbach (2011a, 2011b, 2017), Mizrahi (2013), Wray (2013; 2018), Alai (2017), Niiniluoto (2017), Schech (2019), Ladyman (2021), Park (2022), and Vickers (2023). It is immediately worth noting that the CPI is one argument within a broader family of arguments associated with the name ‘Pessimistic Meta-Induction’. Other arguments associated with that moniker merit their own independent treatment. Examples include but needn’t be limited to Stanford’s (2006) ‘New Pessimistic Induction’, Frost-Arnold’s (2019) ‘Misleading Evidence Induction’, and Achinstein’s (2023) version that inductively predicts disconfirmatory evidence against scientific speculations. Each argument poses a different induction that advances different concerns about the epistemic weight afforded by aspects of scientific inquiry. This family of concerns is at least as old as Montaigne’s (1576) ‘Apology for Raymond Sebond’ and its members are sometimes conflated with each other in the literature. Not only are different inductions sometimes conflated, but they are even commonly conflated with Laudan’s (1981) deductive counterexamples to Putnam’s (1978) ‘No Miracles Argument’. For differentiation between Laudan’s argument and the Pessimistic Meta-Induction, see Lyons (2002), Saatsi (2005, 2019), Cartwright et al., (2022, p. 34–35), and Bird (2022, p. 232). In this essay I focus entirely on the CPI, leaving other meta-inductions to receive treatment elsewhere.

  3. This includes the following. First, how one defines the CPI’s reference class. Second, whether we restrict the CPI to have ‘local’ applications to the special sciences only or whether it is less restricted and applied ‘globally’ to science or even philosophy in general. Third, whether the population space from which we sample theories is finite or infinite. Fourth, the failure of the No-Miracles Argument, if indeed it fails. Fifth, whether confirmation holism or non-holism is true. It is a realist custom to advocate for non-holistic ways in which confirmation might distribute throughout a theory. See e.g., Kitcher (1993), Psillos (1999), and Chakravartty (2007). Evidential propagation is thought to be determined in part by the distinction between working and non-working bits of theory. My refutation of the CPI takes no stance on the specifics of evidential propagation throughout a theory. For a more general discussion about holism and associated ideas about the distributive properties of confirmation, see Sober (2000).

  4. Frost-Arnold (2011, 2014) argues that if the realist is correct about contemporary scientific theories, then many mainstream semantic theories imply that terms like “phlogiston” and “miasma” are empty, rendering past theories neither true nor false. In what follows, the reader may use the terms ‘false’ and ‘not true’ interchangeably depending on their favored semantic theory.

  5. Three quick points. First, by ‘best’ I just mean those theories that at some time displayed the realist’s positive epistemic markers to the highest degree. Second, I’m assuming on behalf of the CPI that there is a useful theory/observation distinction ready to hand. For some discussion on this, see Hobbs (1994). Third, we don’t yet need to distinguish between truth and approximate truth until Sect. 3. Until then, for brevity’s sake, I simply use ‘not (even approximately) true’ and ‘untrue’ interchangeably, and the same for ‘approximately true’ and ‘true’.

  6. Note that this merely aims to describe the track record per se. This is not a formally regimented representation of the inductive inference rule itself. For discussion on the latter, see McGrew and McGrew (2007, p. 138–160) and Sober (2008, p. 19–24).

  7. These commitments are variously mentioned in van Fraassen (1980, p. 8; 1998, p. 213), Musgrave (1988, p. 234), and Psillos (1999, p. xvii).

  8. For just a few examples, see Hesse (1976, p. 266), Kitcher (1993, p. 137), Hobbs (1994, p. 174), Leplin (1997, p. 141–142), Lewis (2001, p. 372), and Lange (2002, p. 281–282). This phrase or something equivalent is omnipresent within the literature.

  9. See Weston (1992) and Hájek (2007). Hájek makes this point in the context of philosophical theorizing.

  10. I consider another way to interpret it in Sect. 5.

  11. I use the term ‘data’ to refer to the relatum in the confirmation relation that plays the role of foreground information. The term ‘evidence’ is typically used to refer to this relatum. I opted not to use that term since an aim of this paper is to show that such foreground information cannot amount to genuine evidence in the first place. While ‘data’ is used differently in other contexts, it is best suited for my purposes here. It conveys foreground information that is taken for granted but leaves open the question of whether it can make a difference to hypotheses.

  12. For proofs, see Appendices A and B. Note also that it isn’t just our best quantitative theories of evidence that satisfy the Converse Entailment Restriction. Popperian confirmation skeptics likewise accept the Converse Entailment Restriction since they hold that H is disconfirmed by D exactly if H and D are logically inconsistent and D has been empirically established. To Popperians, the only way to get disconfirmation is full falsification. So, the condition specified in the antecedent above would be just another way that disconfirmation fails in Popperian eyes.

  13. For a proof, see Appendix C.

  14. For advocates of comparative truth-likeness broadly speaking, see Putnam (1975, p. 118–119), Newton-Smith (1981, p. 39), Boyd (1984, p. 41–42), Leplin (1984, p. 202–212), and Psillos (1999, p. 276).

  15. A similar issue is anticipated by Augustine (1995) in his objection to Ciceronian Skepticism. In his Against the Academicians, Augustine writes: ‘Please pay the closest attention…If a man unacquainted with your father were to see your brother and assert that he is like your father, won’t he seem to you crazy or simple minded?’ [2.7.16.20]. Augustine’s point is that one needs a standard of comparison to make proper ascriptions of truth-likeness.

  16. For examples of these types of conditionals in use, see Lyons (2002, 2006), Vickers (2017), Hricko (2021), and Tulodziecki (2021). For a method that is supposed to epistemically justify these conditionals—for more than one version of the pessimistic induction—see Stanford (2018). Lastly, these two conditionals are worded in a somewhat cumbersome manner. This is intentional since it makes the conditionals either fully true or false and thus amenable to standard probabilistic treatment if one so desired. This trick for transforming verisimilitude claims into truth claims is used by Bird (2007, p. 76–78).

  17. This principle is a mainstay in confirmation theory. It tells us not to throw away any evidence, mandating against misevaluations of D. See Carnap (1950, p. 211–213) as well as Sober and Barrett (2020).

  18. Possible objection: the CPI shouldn’t bring Bn and Pn to bear period. Reply: that is surely incorrect. Insofar as the CPI is meant to put realism to the test, realists must be able to use the full ambit of their commitments to see if the putative structural problem with realism is genuine.

  19. Objection: there is plenty of mystery in scientific reasoning (e.g., the confirmational value of peer review). Reply: to defuse the analogy I need only identify a difference in kind such that the negative aspects of the society can plausibly serve as the basis for my ‘guilt by association’ explanation for why it seemed that Jones’s final rejoinder was illicit, without having those same negative aspects map onto genuine science. The aspects of science that eliminate error suffice for this. Even if there are remaining questions about scientific reasoning, we can at least say that error identification is possible and even common there. Not so for the black-box method. We have no positive conception of the box’s inner circuitry, so we can’t identify any such bits as sources of error. Cumulative error elimination makes it doubtful that successive iterations of scientific theorizing are mutually independent. The black-box, however, straightforwardly conforms to toy models of induction—e.g., coin-flipping—with independent successive trials. Note though, that I do not appeal to these dynamic aspects of science to refute the CPI proper, like Leplin (1997, p. 141), Lipton (2000, p. 204), Doppelt (2007, p. 111), Devitt (2010, p. 96–98), Roush (2010, p. 34), Fahrbach (2011a, 2011b, 2017), Mizrahi (2013), and Park (2022, p. 32). My appeal aims simply to break the analogy between the marble society and science.

  20. Reflection on these four dubious features reveals that they are properties of the track record itself which is conceptually prior to any confirmational role it plays. This implies that these same issues manifest whether one considers the disconfirmation or base rate interpretations of the CPI that use a true/false binary.

  21. We do not know which historical theories will be shaved off ~ Hn and relocated to K prior to historical investigation. That varies from world to world. What we do know a priori is that whatever theories get shaved off from ~ Hn and relocated to K in a well-defined induction, the resulting ~ Hn* will imply whatever historical series that world contains. The inevitability of implication regardless of world-specific detail is my point.

  22. Consider also that the so-called reference class problem for induction (and its corresponding candidate solutions) is entirely motivated by the fact that the specific choice of reference class is a substantive matter since it can alter whether the track record has positive or negative bearing on the inductive hypothesis. Pessimists like Hobbs (1994, p. 185–186) and Wray (2013) take care to specify the right reference class, and their adversaries display no shortage of attempts to ‘limn’ the historical list of theories by advocating for ever more specific formulations of historical realist commitments.

  23. Possible retort: the logical relationships within the argument are a feature rather than a bug once the argument is shorn of any pretense to empiricality. My reply: this innovation would cease to even resemble the argument of interest that has been discussed since the time of Montaigne. Consideration of an argument which is that different would take us beyond the remit of this paper.

  24. For discussions on different philosophically significant notions of statistical ‘randomness’, see Kyburg (1974, p. 216–246), Levi (1980, p. 392–398), Campbell and Franklin (2004), and McGrew and McGrew (2007, p. 148–153). The point that I make in what follows is not affected by the question of whether randomness is a property of sampling procedures or a property of the samplers’ knowledge states.

  25. Mizrahi (2013) applies a randomization device to the historical record after noticing that few seem to be concerned with proper procedure. But the epistemic role of his procedure is downstream from the problem source.

  26. See for example Fahrbach (2011a, 2011b, 2017) and Park (2022, p. 28–29).

  27. This example is borrowed from Titelbaum (2022, p. 198).

  28. This diagnosis is restricted to the CPI proper. In the Golden Marble Society’s meta-induction, the problem arose from the property of uniqueness.

  29. For other versions of the Pessimistic Meta-Induction, see footnote 2.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (2023). Scientific speculation and evidential progress. In Y. Shan (Ed.), New philosophical perspectives on scientific progress (pp. 355–273). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt’s a viable solution? Synthese, 194, 3267–3290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (386/1995). Against the academicians and the teacher. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.

  • Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs, 41, 64–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2022). Knowing science. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburne, S. (2002). Realism: Deconstructing the debate. Ratio, 15(2), 111–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1984). The current status of scientific realism. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 41–82). University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, S., and Franklin, J. (2004). Randomness and the justification of induction. Synthese, 138(1), 79–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). The logical foundations of probability. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., Hardie, J., Montuschi, E., Soleiman, M., & Thresher, A. (2022). The tangle of science: Reliability beyond method, rigour, and objectivty. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2010). Putting metaphysics first: Essays on metaphysics and epistemology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2011). Are unconceived alternatives a problem for scientific realism? Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42, 285–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doppelt, G. (2007). Reconstructing scientific realism to rebut the pessimistic meta-induction. Philosophy of Science, 74, 96–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahrbach, L. (2011a). How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese, 180, 139–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahrbach, L. (2011b). Theory change and degree of success. Philosophy of Science, 78, 1283–1292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahrbach, L. (2017). Scientific revolutions and the explosion of scientific evidence. Synthese, 194, 5039–5072.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frost-Arnold, G. (2011). From the pessimistic induction to semantic anti-realism. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1131–1142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frost-Arnold, G. (2014). Can the pessimistic induction be saved from semantic anti-realism about scientific theory? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(3), 521–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frost-Arnold, G. (2019). How to be a historically motivated antirealist: The problem of misleading evidence. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 906–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2007). My philosophical position says p and I don’t believe p. In M. Green & J. Williams (Eds.), Moore’s paradox: New essays on belief, rationality, and the first person (pp. 218–230). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1976). Truth and the growth of scientific knowledge. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 261–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, J. (1994). A limited defense of the pessimistic induction. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45, 171–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1982). Probability and evidence. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hricko, J. (2021). What can the discovery of boron tell us about the scientific realism debate? In T. Lyons & P. Vickers (Eds.), Contemporary scientific realism: The challenge from the history of science (pp. 31–55). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1757/2006). Moral philosophy. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (ed). Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1992/2000). The trouble with the historical philosophy of science. In J. Conant and J. Haugeland (Eds.), The road since structure: Philosophical essays, 1970–1993, with an autobiographical interview (pp. 105–120). University of Chicago Press.

  • Kukla, A., & Walmsley, J. (2004). A theory’s predictive success does not warrant belief in the unobservable entities in postulates. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 177–132). Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H., Jr. (1974). The logical foundations of statistical inference. D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2021). Structure not selection. In T. Lyons & P. Vickers (Eds.), Contemporary scientific realism: The challenge from the history of science (pp. 239–256). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2002). Baseball, pessimistic inductions and the turnover fallacy. Analysis, 62(4), 281–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1984). Truth and scientific progress. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 193–217). University of California Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1980). The enterprise of knowledge. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2001). Why the pessimistic induction is a fallacy. Synthese, 129, 371–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2000). Tracking track records. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 74, 179–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2002). Scientific realism and the pessimistic meta-modus tollens. In S. Clarke & T. Lyons (Eds.), Recent themes in the philosophy of science: Scientific realism and common sense (pp. 63–90). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2006). Scientific realism and the strategema de divide et impera. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 537–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2010). Inductions, red herrings, and the best explanation for the mixed record of science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(4), 803–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D., & Callender, C. (2004). Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science, 71, 320–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrew, L., & McGrew, T. (2007). Internalism and epistemology: The architecture of reason. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190, 3209–3226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montaigne, M. (1576/1965). Apology for Raymond Sebond. In The complete essays of Montaigne (pp. 318–457) (D. Frame, Trans.). Stanford University Press.

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In Nola (ed) Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229–252). Kluwer.

  • Newton-Smith, W. (1981). The rationality of science. Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2017). Optimistic realism about scientific progress. Synthese, 194, 3291–3309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R. (2008). The optimistic meta-induction and ontological continuity: The case of the electron. In L. Soler, H. Sankey, & P. Hoyningen-Huene (Eds.), Rethinking scientific change and theory comparison: Stabilities, ruptures, incomensurabilities? (pp. 159–202). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2010). Realism, Ramsey sentences and the pessimistic meta-induction. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 375–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pareto, V. (1935). The mind and society, Vol. 1 (Arthur Livingston, Trans.). New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

  • Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). How not to talk about meaning. In Philosophical papers Vol. 2, Mind, language and reality (pp. 117–131). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roush, S. (2010). Optimism about the pessimistic induction. In P. D. Magnus & J. Busch (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of science (pp. 29–58). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2005). On the pessimistic induction and two fallacies. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1088–1098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2019). Historical inductions, old and new. Synthese, 196, 3979–3993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schech, E. (2019). Historical inductions meet the material theory. Philosophy of Science, 86, 918–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (2000). Self-dependent justification without circularity. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 287–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2000). Quine’s two dogmas. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 74, 237–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., & Barrett, M. (2020). The requirement of total evidence: A reply to Epstein’s critique. Philosophy of Science, 87, 191–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. (2003). Pyrrhic victories for scientific realism. Journal of Philosophy, 100, 553–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. (2018). Unconceived alternatives and the strategy of historical ostension. In J. Saatsi (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of scientific realism (pp. 212–224). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Titelbaum, M. (2022). Fundamentals of bayesian epistemology 2: Arguments, challenges. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tulodziecki, D. (2021). Theoretical continuity, approximate truth, and the pessimistic meta-induction: Revisiting the miasma theory. In T. Lyons & P. Vickers (Eds.), Contemporary scientific realism: The challenge from the history of science (pp. 11–32). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1998). The agnostic subtly probabilified. Analysis, 58, 212–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, P. (2017). Understanding the selective realist defence against the PMI. Synthese, 194, 3221–3232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, P. (2023). Identifying future-proof science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weston, T. (1992). Approximate truth and scientific realism. Philosophy of Science, 59, 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1994). How to remain (reasonably) optimistic: Scientific realism and the ‘luminiferous ether.’ PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1, 334–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. (2013). The pessimistic induction and the exponential growth of science reassessed. Synthese, 190, 4321–4330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. (2018). Resisting scientific realism. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Alan Sidelle, Peter Vranas, Elliott Sober, Hayley Clatterbuck, Meryem Keskin, Christopher Pincock, Keshav Singh, Peter Tan, Paul Kelley, Nate Lauffer, and two anonymous referees at Erkenntnis for helpful feedback on this essay. Thanks also to Lindsey Brainard and Kenneth Boyce for their helpful comments at the 2022 APA Central Division Meeting’s symposium on this paper. Lastly, special thanks to Mike Titelbaum for his wisdom throughout this essay’s development.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Cronin.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix A

The following is a proof that Bayesianism satisfies the Converse Entailment Restriction. Here, PrK(-) and PrK(- | -) are probability functions with the background corpus encoded into them.

1. Suppose that there is a well-defined probability distribution D1 containing logically consistent data D, hypothesis H, and total background corpus K

 

where H&K╞ D

Assumption

2. D disconfirms H relative to K iff PrK(H) > PrK(H|D)

Bayesian Assumption

3. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H)PrK(D|H)/PrK(D)

Bayes’s Theorem

4. PrK(D) = PrK(H)PrK(D|H) + PrK(~ H)PrK(D|~ H)

Law of Total Probability

5. Either PrK(H) < PrK(D|H), PrK(H) = PrK(D|H), or PrK(H) > PrK(D|H)

Tautology

6. PrK(D|H) = 1

1 Math

    7. PrK(H) > PrK(D|H)

Assume for Reductio

    8. PrK(H) > 1

6, 7 Identity Substitution

    9. It is false that PrK(H) > 1

Maximality Theorem

    10. PrK(H) > 1 and it is false that PrK(H) > 1

8, 9 Conjunction Introduction

11. It is false that PrK(H) > PrK(D|H)

7–10 Reductio

12. Either PrK(H) < PrK(D|H) or PrK(H) = PrK(D|H)

5, 11 Disjunctive Syllogism

     13. PrK(H) = PrK(D|H)

Assume for Conditional Proof

     14. PrK(H) = 1

6, 13 Identity Substitution

     15. PrK(H|D) = 1 × PrK(D|H)/PrK(D)

3, 14 Identity Substitution

     16. PrK(H|D) = 1 × 1/PrK(D)

6, 15 Identity Substitution

     17. PrK(H|D) = 1/PrK(D)

16 Math

     18. PrK(H|D) = 1/PrK(H)PrK(D|H) + PrK(~ H)PrK(D|~ H)

4, 17 Identity Substitution

     19. PrK(H|D) = 1/1 × PrK(D|H) + PrK(~ H)PrK(D|~ H)

16, 18 Identity Substitution

     20. PrK(H|D) = 1/1 × 1 + PrK(~ H)PrK(D|~ H)

6, 19 Identity Substitution

     21. PrK(~ H) = 1-PrK(H)

Negation Theorem

     22. PrK(~ H) = 0

14, 21 Math

     23. PrK(H|D) = 1/1 × 1 + [0 × PrK(D|~ H)]

20, 22 Identity Substitution

     24. PrK(H|D) = 1

23 Math

     25. PrK(H) = PrK(H|D)

14, 24 Identity Transitivity

     26. It is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

2, 25 Biconditional Exchange

27. If PrK(H) = PrK(D|H), then it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

13–26 Conditional Proof

     28. It is false that PrK(H) < PrK(D|H) only if it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

Assume for Reductio

     29. PrK(H) < PrK(D|H) and it is not false that D disconfirms H relative to K

28 Negated Conditional

     30. It is not false that D disconfirms H relative to K

29 Conjunction Elimination

     31. D disconfirms H relative to K

30 Double Negation

     32. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H) × 1/PrK(D)

3, 6 Identity Substitution

     33. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H)/PrK(D)

32 Math

     34. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H&D)/PrK(D)

Ratio Formula

     35. PrK(H&D)/PrK(D) = PrK(H)/PrK(D)

33, 34 Identity Transitivity

     36. PrK(H&D) = PrK(H)

35 Math

     37. PrK(H) = PrK(H&D) + PrK(H& ~ D)

Decomposition Theorem

     38. PrK(H& ~ D) = 0

36, 37 Math

     39. PrK(D) = PrK(D&H) + PrK(D& ~ H)

Decomposition Theorem

     40. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H&D) + PrK(H& ~ D)/PK(D)

33, 37 Identity Substitution

     41. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H&D) + PrK(H& ~ D)/PrK(D&H) + PrK(D& ~ H)

39, 40 Identity Substitution

     42. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H&D) + 0/PrK(D&H) + PrK(D& ~ H)

38, 41 Identity Substitution

     43. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H&D) + 0/PrK(H&D) + PrK(D& ~ H)

42 Commutation

     44. PrK(H|D) = 0/PrK(D& ~ H)

43 Math

     45. PrK(H&D)/PrK(D) = 0/PrK(D& ~ H)

34, 44 Identity Substitution

     46. PrK(H&D)PrK(D& ~ H) = PrK(D) × 0

45 Math

     47. PrK(H&D)PrK(D& ~ H) = 0

46 Math

     48. PrK(D& ~ H) = 0/PrK(H&D)

47 Math

     49. PrK(H&D) ≥ 0

Tautology

           50. PrK(H&D) = 0

Assume for Reductio

           51. PrK(D& ~ H) = 0/0

48, 50 Identity Substitution

           52. PrK(D& ~ H) is not well-defined

51 Math

           53. PrK(D& ~ H) is well-defined and PrK(D& ~ H) is not well-defined

1, 52 Conjunction Introduction

     54. PrK(H&D) ≠ 0

50–53 Reductio

     55. PrK(H&D) > 0

49, 54 Disjunctive Syllogism

     56. PrK(D& ~ H) = 1

48, 55 Math

     57. PrK(H|D) = 0/1

44, 56 Identity Substitution

     58. PrK(H|D) = 0

57 Math

     59. It is false that PrK(H) < 0

Non-Negativity Axiom

     60. PrK(D) < PrK(D|H) iff PrK(H) < PrK(H|D)

Confirmation Symmetry

     61. PrK(D) < PrK(D|H) iff PrK(H) < 0

58, 60 Identity Substitution

     62. Either PrK(D) < PrK(D|H), PrK(D) = PrK(D|H), or PrK(D) > PrK(D|H)

Tautology

     63. Either PrK(D) < 1, PrK(D) = 1, or PrK(D) > 1

6, 62 Identity Substitution

     64. It is false that PrK(D) > 1

Maximality Theorem

     65. Either PrK(D) < 1, PrK(D) = 1

63, 64 Disjunctive Syllogism

           66. PrK(D) = 1

Assume for Reductio

           67. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H)/1

33, 66 Identity Substitution

           68. PrK(H|D) = PrK(H)

67 Math

           69. It is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

2, 68 Biconditional Exchange

           70. D disconfirms H relative to K and It is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

31, 69 Conjunction Introduction

     71. PrK(D) ≠ 1

66–70 Reductio

     72. PrK(D) < 1

65, 71 Disjunctive Syllogism

     73. PrK(D) < 1 iff PK(H) < 0

61, 72 Identity Substitution

     74. PrK(H) < 0

72, 73 Biconditional Exchange

     75. PrK(H) < 0 and it is false that PrK(H) < 0

59, 74 Conjunction Introduction

76. PrK(H) < PrK(D|H) only if it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

28–75 Reductio

77. PrK(H) = PrK(D|H) only if it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K, and PrK(H) < PrK(D|H) only if it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

27, 76 Conjunction Introduction

78. Either it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K, or it is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

 

12, 77 Disjunctive Dilemma

79. It is false that D disconfirms H relative to K

78 Tautology

80. For any well-defined probability distribution D containing logically consistent data D, hypothesis H, and background knowledge K: if H&K╞ D, then

 

    D does not disconfirm H relative to K.

Appendix B

The following is a proof that Likelihoodism satisfies the Converse Entailment Restriction.

1. Suppose that there is a well-defined probability distribution D1 containing logically consistent data D, competing hypotheses H1 and H2, and total

 

    background corpus K where H1&K╞ D

Assumption

2. D disfavors hypothesis H1 to H2 iff PrK(D|H1) < PrK(D|H2)

Likelihoodist Assumption

3. PrK(D|H1) = 1

1 Math

4. Either PrK(D|H2) < 1, PrK(D|H2) = 1, or PrK(D|H2) > 1

Tautology

5. It is false that PrK(D|H2) > 1

Maximality Theorem

6. PrK(D|H2) < 1 or PrK(D|H2) = 1

4, 5 Disjunctive Syllogism

    7. PrK(D|H2) = 1

Assume for Conditional Proof

    8. PrK(D|H1) = PrK(D|H2)

3, 7 Math

    9. It is false that D disfavors H1 to H2

2, 8 Biconditional Exchange

10. If PrK(D|H2) = 1, then it is false that D disfavors H1 to H2

7–9 Conditional Proof

    11. PrK(D|H2) < 1

Assume for Conditional Proof

    12. PrK(D|H1) > PrK(D|H2)

3, 11 Math

    13. It is false that D disfavors H1 to H2

2, 12 Biconditional Exchange

14. If PrK(D|H2) < 1, then it is false that D disfavors H1 to H2

11–13 Conditional Proof

15. PrK(D|H2) = 1 only if it is false that D disfavors H1 to H2, and

 

      PrK(D|H2) < 1 only if it is false that D disfavors H1 to H2

10, 14 Conjunction Introduction

16. It is false that D disfavors H1 to H2 or it is false that

 

      D disfavors H1 to H2

6, 15 Disjunctive Dilemma

17. It is false that D disfavors H1 to H2

16 Tautology

18. For any well-defined probability distribution D containing logically consistent data D, competing hypotheses H1 and H2, and total

 

    background corpus K where H1&K╞ D, then D does not disfavor H1 to H2 relative to K.

Appendix C

Here is a derivation of GER from the Converse Entailment Restriction. For any hypothesis H, data D, total background corpus K and its proper subset K*:

1. If H&K╞ D, then D does not disconfirm H relative to K

Assumption

2. K╞ K*

Tautology

    3. H&K*╞ D

Assume for Conditional Proof

        4. H&K

Assume for Conditional Proof

        5. K

4 Conjunction Elimination

        6. K*

2, 5 Modus Ponens

        7. H

4 Conjunction Elimination

        8. H&K*

6, 7 Conjunction Introduction

        9. D

3, 8 Modus Ponens

    10. H&K╞ D

5–9 Conditional Proof

    11. D does not disconfirm H relative to K

1, 10 Modus Ponens

12. If H&K*╞ D, then D does not disconfirm H relative to K

3–11 Conditional Proof

13. For any hypothesis H, data D, total background corpus K and its subset K*: If H&K*╞ D, then D does not disconfirm H relative to K

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cronin, P. An A Priori Refutation of the Classical Pessimistic Induction. Erkenn (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00832-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00832-5

Navigation