Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Patient Similarity in the Era of Precision Medicine: A Philosophical Analysis

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to N. Goodman, the Carnapian notion of similarity is useless in science and without interest for philosophy. In our paper we suggest that, given the current role that the notion of similarity has in managing biomedical big data, this drastic position should be revised, and similarity should be provided a scientifically useful philosophical interpretation. With the advent of the new sequencing technologies, imaging technologies and with the improvements of health records, the number of genomics, post-genomics and clinical data has exponentially increased. The deluge of data has urged, among others, to devise a new way of stratifying patients. A solution has been found and it is based exactly on the notion of similarity. By discussing two examples focusing on similarity among breast cancer patients, in the paper we illustrate such a use, and analyze it from a philosophical standpoint by resorting to A. Tversky’s features matching approach. We believe that the latter can foster some better understanding of the meaning and current use of similarity in the context of biomedical big data, and that, therefore, be the focus of further reflections in the philosophy of science, in particular in the philosophy of biomedicine.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is worth recalling that the similarity notion based on the metric came out in geometry around 1906, thanks to the work of the French mathematicians René Fréchet (even if the name is due to Felix Hausdorff) when he discussed the notion of distance between two points of a topological space. Carnap’s work was very close to the dawn of the mathematical birth of that notion.

  2. We do not discuss here the limits and the potentialities of precision medicine, in particular if precision medicine is really precise or if it is always ethically praiseworthy (both at individual and global level). We do not even face the question whether a more proper definition of precision medicine exists, or which its historical roots are. This is not the right place to face these issues. For our sake, however, we pragmatically accept the well-known definition offered by the US National Research Council, according to which “precision medicine is ‘an emerging approach for disease treatment and prevention that takes into account individual variability in genes, environment, and lifestyle for each person’, [meant] […] to predict more accurately which treatment and prevention strategies for a particular disease will work in which groups of people”: https://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/ Precision Medicine; on the relations between precision and personalized medicine, https://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/primer/precisionmedicine/precisionvspersonalized. See also https://www.nih.gov/research-training/allofus-research-program (Accessed 30 April 2017). See Barilan, Brusa and Ciechanover 2021.

  3. PAM50 Prosigna® is a tumour-profiling test that helps determine the benefit of using chemotherapy in addition to hormone therapy for some estrogen receptor-positive (ER-positive) and HER2-negative breast cancers.

  4. A tumour is said to have had a pCR if, after surgery, no residual cancer cells remain.

  5. For a more technical approach, see Zhu et al. (2016).

  6. This is also the reason why here the distance can be negative, while one of the conditions in the original metric space introduced in geometry and discussed by Carnap was that it has to be positive: a statistical space realized with biomedical data is different from an abstract topological space endowed with a metric.

  7. Due to space limits, we do not show here that also the independence conditions is satisfied.

  8. For other philosophical applications of the FMA, and, specifically, on using similarity for vagueness and identity, see Douven and Decock (2011).

References

  • Ali, R. H., Rueda, O., Chin, S.-F., et al. (2014). Genome-driven integrated classification of breast cancer validated in over 7,500 samples. Genome Biology, 15, 431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barilan, M. Y., Brusa, M., & Ciechanover, A. (Eds.). (2021). Can precision medicine be personal: Can personalized medicine be precise? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boniolo, G. (2017). Patchwork narratives for tumour heterogeneity. In H. Leitgeb, I. Niiniluoto, E. Sober, & P. Seppälä (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science—Proceedings of the 15th international congress (pp. 311–24). London: College Publications.

  • Boniolo, G., & Nathan, M. J. (Eds.). (2017). Philosophy of molecular medicine. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S.-A. (2016). Patient similarity: Emerging concepts in systems and precision medicine. Frontiers in Physiology, 7, 561. https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2016.00561

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruna, A., Rueda, O. M., Greenwood, W., et al. (2016). A biobank of breast cancer explants with preserved intra-tumor heterogeneity to screen anticancer compounds. Cell, 167, 260–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1928). Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Berlin: Weltkreisverlag. Repr. Hamburg: Meiner [1961] (and later). English translation by Rolf A. George: The Logical Construction of the World, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul [1967].

  • Carrara, M., & Morato, V. (2011). Toward a Formal Account of Similarity and Family Resemblance for Technical Functions. In P. E. Vermaas & V. Dignum (Eds.), Formal ontologies meet industry (pp. 63–74). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curtis, C., Shah, S., Chin, S.-F., et al. (2012). The genomic and transcriptomic architecture of 2,000 breast tumours reveals novel subgroups. Nature, 486, 346–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dai, L., Zhu, H., & Liu, D. (2020). Patient similarity: methods and applications. arXiv:2012.01976 [cs.LG].

  • Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2011). Similarity after Goodman. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 61–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, J., & Flores, L. J. (2015). The risk GP model: The standard model of prediction in medicine. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical. Sciences, 54, 49–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2004). Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1972). Seven strictures on similarity. In N. Goodman (Ed.), Problems and projects (pp. 437–446). Indianapolis/New York: Bobbs-Merrill.

  • Guinney, J., Dienstmann, R., Wang, X., et al. (2015). The consensus molecular subtypes of colorectal cancer. Nature Medicine, 21, 1350–1416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli, S. (2016). Data-centric biology: A philosophical study. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morganella, S., Alexandrov, L. B., Glodzik, D., et al. (2016). The topography of mutational processes in breast cancer genomes. Nature Communications, 7, 11383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Network, C. G. A. (2015). Genomic classification of cutaneous melanoma. Cell, 16, 1681–1696. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2015.05.044

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nik-Zainal, S., Van Loo, P., Wedge, D. C., et al. (2012). The life history of 21 breast cancers. Cell, 149, 994–1007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nik-Zainal, S., Davies, H., Staaf, J., et al. (2016). Landscape of somatic mutations in 560 Bbreast cancer whole-genome sequences. Nature, 534, 47–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pai, S., & Bader, G. D. (2018). Patient similarity networks for precision medicine. Journal of Molecular Biology. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jmb.2018.05.037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parimbelli, E., Marini, S., Sacchi, L., & Bellazzi, R. (2018). Patient similarity for precision medicine: A systematic review. Journal of Biomedical Informatics. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbi.2018.06.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, B., Chin, S.-F., Rueda, O. M., et al. (2016). The somatic mutation profiles of 2,433 breast cancers refine their genomic and transcriptomic landscapes. Nature Communications, 7, 11479. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms11479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, G. A., Kim, J., Al-Ahmadie, H., et al. (2017). Comprehensive molecular characterization of muscle-invasive bladder cancer. Cell, 171, 540-556.e25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross-Adams, H., et al. (2015). Integration of copy number and transcriptomics provides risk stratification in prostate cancer: A discovery and validation cohort study. eBioMedicine, 2, 1133–1144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russnes, H. G., Lingjærde, O. C., Anne-LiseBørresen-Dale, A. L., Caldas, C., et al. (2017). Breast cancer molecular stratification: From intrinsic subtypes to integrative clusters. American Journal of Pathology, 187, 2152–2162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sánchez-Valle, J., et al. (2020). Interpreting molecular similarity between patients as a determinant of disease comorbidity relationships. Nature Communications, 11, 2854. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-020-16540-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. (2013). Are species real? An essay in the metaphysics of science. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. (2015). Natural kindness. The British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 66, 375–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strasser, B. (2019). Collecting experiments: Making big data biology. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tan, P.-N., et al. (2017). Introduction to data mining (2nd ed.). Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. (1977). Features of similarity. Psychological Review, 84(4), 327–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallmann, C. (2017). A Bayesian solution to the conflict of narrowness and precision in direct inference. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48, 485–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallmann, C., & Williamson, J. (2017). Four approaches to the reference class problem. In G. Hofer-Szabó & L. Wroński (Eds.), Making it formally explicit: probability, causality and indeterminism (pp. 61–81). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weddell, N., Pajic, M., Patch, A.-M., et al. (2015). Whole genomes redefine the mutational landscape of pancreatic cancer. Nature, 518(26), 495–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Z., et al. (2016). Measuring patient similarities via a deep architecture with medical concept embedding. In 2016 IEEE 16th international conference on data mining. https://doi.org/10.1109/ICDM.2016.0086.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We wish to thank the referees of Erkenntnis for their comments and suggestions on preliminary versions of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Massimiliano Carrara.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boniolo, G., Campaner, R. & Carrara, M. Patient Similarity in the Era of Precision Medicine: A Philosophical Analysis. Erkenn 88, 2911–2932 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00483-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00483-w

Navigation